•  58
    On the completeness of non-philonian stoic logic
    History and Philosophy of Logic 16 (1): 39-64. 1995.
    The majority of formal accounts attribute to Stoic logicians the classical truth-functional understanding of the material conditional and exclusive disjunction.These interpretations were disputed,...
  •  79
    A note on scale invariance
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 34 (1): 49-55. 1983.
    A note on scale invariance.
  •  206
    Not every truth has a truthmaker II
    Analysis 73 (3): 473-481. 2013.
    A proof employing no semantic terms is offered in support of the claim that there can be truths without truthmakers. The logical resources used in the proof are weak but do include the structural rule Contraction
  •  54
    Is there a logic of confirmation transfer?
    Erkenntnis 53 (3): 309-335. 2000.
    This article begins by exploring a lost topic in the philosophy of science:the properties of the relations evidence confirming h confirmsh'' and, more generally, evidence confirming each ofh1, h2, ..., hm confirms at least one of h1, h2,ldots;, hn''.The Bayesian understanding of confirmation as positive evidential relevanceis employed throughout. The resulting formal system is, to say the least, oddlybehaved. Some aspects of this odd behaviour the system has in common withsome of the non-classic…Read more
  •  217
    The thesis that, in a system of natural deduction, the meaning of a logical constant is given by some or all of its introduction and elimination rules has been developed recently in the work of Dummett, Prawitz, Tennant, and others, by the addition of harmony constraints. Introduction and elimination rules for a logical constant must be in harmony. By deploying harmony constraints, these authors have arrived at logics no stronger than intuitionist propositional logic. Classical logic, they maint…Read more
  •  5
    Reviews (review)
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 35 (1): 312-313. 1984.
  •  150
    Bruno de finetti and the logic of conditional events
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 48 (2): 195-232. 1997.
    This article begins by outlining some of the history—beginning with brief remarks of Quine's—of work on conditional assertions and conditional events. The upshot of the historical narrative is that diverse works from various starting points have circled around a nexus of ideas without convincingly tying them together. Section 3 shows how ideas contained in a neglected article of de Finetti's lead to a unified treatment of the topics based on the identification of conditional events as the object…Read more
  •  233
    On Gödel Sentences and What They Say
    Philosophia Mathematica 15 (2): 193-226. 2007.
    Proofs of Gödel's First Incompleteness Theorem are often accompanied by claims such as that the gödel sentence constructed in the course of the proof says of itself that it is unprovable and that it is true. The validity of such claims depends closely on how the sentence is constructed. Only by tightly constraining the means of construction can one obtain gödel sentences of which it is correct, without further ado, to say that they say of themselves that they are unprovable and that they are tru…Read more
  •  4
    Review of Ralph Charles Sutherland Walker: Kant: the arguments of the philosophers (review)
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 34 (3): 312-313. 1983.
  •  27
    Annabel and the bookmaker: An everyday tale of bayesian folk
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 69 (1). 1991.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  14
    Languages of Possibility: An essay in Philosophical Logic
    Philosophical Books 31 (4): 222-224. 1992.
  •  155
    Tarski on truth and its definition
    In Timothy Childers, Petr Kolft & Vladimir Svoboda (eds.), Logica '96: Proceedings of the 10th International Symposium, Filosofia. pp. 198-210. 1997.
    Of his numerous investigations ... Tarski was most proud of two: his work on truth and his design of an algorithm in 1930 to decide the truth or falsity of any sentence of the elementary theory of the high school Euclidean geometry. [...] His mathematical treatment of the semantics of languages and the concept of truth has had revolutionary consequences for mathematics, linguistics, and philosophy, and Tarski is widely thought of as the man who "defined truth". The seeming simplicity of his famo…Read more
  •  101
    While there is now considerable experimental evidence that, on the one hand, participants assign to the indicative conditional as probability the conditional probability of consequent given antecedent and, on the other, they assign to the indicative conditional the “defective truth-table” in which a conditional with false antecedent is deemed neither true nor false, these findings do not in themselves establish which multi-premise inferences involving conditionals participants endorse. A natural…Read more
  •  119
    Various natural deduction formulations of classical, minimal, intuitionist, and intermediate propositional and first-order logics are presented and investigated with respect to satisfaction of the separation and subformula properties. The technique employed is, for the most part, semantic, based on general versions of the Lindenbaum and Lindenbaum–Henkin constructions. Careful attention is paid to which properties of theories result in the presence of which rules of inference, and to restriction…Read more
  •  42
    Existence and Identity in Free Logic: Two Comments
    Mind 116 (464): 1079-1082. 2007.
    Professor Tennant and I agree on much regarding the proof-theoretic semantics of free logic. Here I point to two issues, one on which we disagree, the other on which I find it hard to say how closely we may agree. The first concerns the exact content of Tennant's Rule of Atomic Denotation. The second concerns the nature of assumptions whose formal counterparts contain parametric occurrences of names
  •  149
    A note on Popper, propensities, and the two-slit experiment
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 36 (1): 66-70. 1985.
  •  48
    Notes on Teaching Logic
    Discourse: Learning and Teaching in Philosophical and Religious Studies 4 (1): 137-158
    hese notes don’t reach any conclusions. Their purpose is to point to issues one needs to think through seriously when thinking about logic teaching. They indicate some of the relevant literature where some of these issues are addressed, but they also raise points that seem to have been overlooked. They aim to promote informed discussion. That indeed was their origin: they are descended from an internal discussion document prepared a few years ago when the then Department of Philosophy at the Uni…Read more
  •  159
    Tarski, truth and model theory
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 99 (2). 1999.
    As Wilfrid Hodges has observed, there is no mention of the notion truth-in-a-model in Tarski's article 'The Concept of Truth in Formalized Languages'; nor does truth make many appearances in his papers on model theory from the early 1950s. In later papers from the same decade, however, this reticence is cast aside. Why should Tarski, who defined truth for formalized languages and pretty much founded model theory, have been so reluctant to speak of truth in a model? What might explain the change …Read more
  •  34
    Review of I nference to the Best Explanation (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 53 (4): 970-972. 1993.
  •  62
    Hartry field on measurement and intrinsic explanation
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 37 (3): 340-346. 1986.
  •  8
    Reviews (review)
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 35 (1): 95-100. 1984.
  •  92
    Belief, Degrees of Belief, and Assertion
    Dialectica 66 (3): 331-349. 2012.
    Starting from John MacFarlane's recent survey of answers to the question ‘What is assertion?’, I defend an account of assertion that draws on elements of MacFarlane's and Robert Brandom's commitment accounts, Timothy Williamson's knowledge norm account, and my own previous work on the normative status of logic. I defend the knowledge norm from recent attacks. Indicative conditionals, however, pose a problem when read along the lines of Ernest Adams' account, an account supported by much work in …Read more
  •  25
    On Tennant's intuitionist relevant logics
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 74 (1). 1996.
    This Article does not have an abstract