Carla Bagnoli

University of Modena and Reggio Emilia
  •  1
    Disclaiming responsibility, voicing disagreements, negotiating boundaries
    Oxford Studies in Agency and Responsibility 7 (1): 283-305. 2021.
    This essay introduces the novel category of “disclaimers” – distinctive normative acts which challenge third-party attributions of responsibility in a community governed by norms of mutual accountability. While the debate focuses on evasive and wrongful refusals to take responsibility for one’s wrongs, this essay argues that disclaimers are fundamental modes of exercising normative powers, whose main functions are demanding recognition, responding to wrongs, voicing disagreement, exiting alienat…Read more
  •  4
    On Richard Moran's Authority and estrangement. Author's reply
    with Josep E. Corbi, Komarine Romdenh-Romluc, Josep L. Prades, Hilan Bensusan, Manuel de Pinedo, and Richard Moran
    Theoria 22 (58). 2007.
  •  66
    Ethical objectivity: The test of time
    Ratio 32 (4): 325-338. 2019.
    A constructivist defense of ethical objectivity in contrast to debunking arguments.
  •  30
    Love’s Luck Knot
    Angelaki: Journal of Theoretical Humanities 25 (1-2): 195-208. 2020.
  •  19
    According to Iris Murdoch, the chief experience in morality is loving attention. Her view calls into question the Kantian account of the standard of moral authority, and ultimately denies that reason might provide moral discernment, validate moral experience, or drive us toward moral progress. Like Kant, Murdoch defines the moral experience as the subjective experience of freedom, which resists any reductivist approach. Unlike Kant, she thinks that this free agency is unprincipled. Some of her a…Read more
  •  27
    Normativity and emotional vulnerability
    Philosophy and Social Criticism 46 (2): 141-151. 2020.
    Are the emotions relevant for the theory of value and normativity? Is there a set of morally correct arrangements of emotions? Current debates are often structured as though there were only two theoretical options to approach these questions, a sentimentalist theory of some sort, which emphasizes the role of emotions in forming ethical behaviour and practical thought, and intellectualist rationalism, which denies that emotions can help at all in generating normativity and contributing to moral v…Read more
  • “Reflective Efficacy. On Neil Sinhababu Humean Nature"
    Rivista Italiana di Filosofia E Psicologia 1 (9): 67-72. 2018.
    This is a contribution to the symposium on Neil Sinhababu Humean Nature.
  •  1
    The practical significance of the categorical imperative
    Oxford Studies in Normative Ethics 11 (1): 177-198. 2021.
    On a standard interpretation, the aim of the formula of universal law is to provide a decision procedure for determining the deontic status of actions. By contrast, this chapter argues for the practical significance of the CI centering on Kant’s account of the dynamics of incentives. This approach avoids some widespread misconceptions about how the CI operates and false expectations about what it promises and delivers. In particular, it explains how it differs from deductive practical inferences…Read more
  • Traditionally, philosophers have focused on whether and how emotions threaten autonomy, insofar as they lie outside the sphere of rational agency. That is, they have conceptualized emotional vulnerability as passivity. Second, they have considered how emotions are insensitive to rational judgment, focusing on cases in which emotions are dissonant or recalcitrant. Third, in recognizing the motivational force of emotions, philosophers have tracked their negative impact on rational deliberation. In…Read more
  •  105
    Authority as a contingency plan
    Philosophical Explorations 22 (2): 130-145. 2019.
    Humean constructivists object to Kantian constructivism that by endorsing the constitutivist strategy, which grounds moral obligations in rational agency, this position discounts the impact of cont...
  • Responsabilità, reciprocità e cooperazione
    Rivista di Filosofia 99 469-475. 2018.
    This article accounts for the relation among the concepts of mutual accountability, cooperation, and reciprocity.
  • This chapter discusses butō dance as an example of improvisation that challenges not only the extant philosophical definitions of improvisation, but also some fundamental presumptions about self-government and agency that are current in action theory. In the first part of the chapter, I identify the main features of butō improvisation, with regard to the nature of its basic movement, and the kind of subjectivity implicated in its generation. I then raise some questions regarding the philosophica…Read more
  •  42
    According to a traditional account, moral cognition is an achievement gained over time by sharing a practice under the guidance and the example of the wise, in analogy with craft and apprenticeship. This model captures an important feature of practical reason, that is, its incompleteness, and highlights our dependence on others in obtaining moral knowledge, coherently with the socially extended mind agenda and recent findings in empirical psychology. However, insofar as it accords to exemplars’ …Read more
  •  71
    Hume Studies Referees 2005–2006
    with Kate Abramson, Donald Ainslie, Lilli Alanen, Julia Annas, Margaret Atherton, Donald Baxter, Martin Bell, Richard Bett, and Colin Bird
    Hume Studies 32 (2): 391-393. 2006.
  •  31
    Respect and Loving Attention
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 33 (4): 483-515. 2003.
    On Kant's view, the feeling of respect is the mark of moral agency, and is peculiar to us, animals endowed with reason. Unlike any other feeling, respect originates in the contemplation of the moral law, that is, the idea of lawful activity. This idea works as a constraint on our deliberation by discounting the pretenses of our natural desires and demoting our selfish maxims. We experience its workings in the guise of respect. Respect shows that from the agent's subjective perspective, morality …Read more
  •  15
    The Appeal of Kantian Intuitionism (review)
    European Journal of Philosophy 17 (1): 152-158. 2009.
    A critical review of R. Audi
  •  351
    The Authority of Reflection
    Theoria: Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia 22 (1): 43-52. 2007.
    This paper examines Moran’s argument for the special authority of the first-person, which revolves around the Self/Other asymmetry and grounds dichotomies such as the practical vs. theoretical, activity vs. passivity, and justificatory vs. explanatory reasons. These dichotomies qualify the self-reflective person as an agent, interested in justifying her actions from a deliberative stance. The Other is pictured as a spectator interested in explaining action from a theoretical stance. The self-ref…Read more
  • Phenomenology of the Aftermath: Ethical Theory and the Intelligibility of Moral Experience
    Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 94 185-212. 2007.
  •  49
    Claiming Responsibility for Action Under Duress
    Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 21 (4): 851-868. 2018.
    This paper argues that to understand the varieties of wrongs done in coercion, we should examine the dynamic normative relation that the coercer establishes with the coerced. The case rests on a critical examination of coercion by threat, which is proved irreducible to psychological inducement by overwhelming motives, obstruction of agency by impaired consent or deprivation of genuine choice. In contrast to physical coercion, coercion by threat requires the coercee’s participation in deliberatio…Read more
  •  106
    The exploration of moral life
    In Justin Broakes (ed.), Iris Murdoch, philosopher, Oxford University Press. 2011.
    The most distinctive feature of Murdoch's philosophical project is her attempt to reclaim the exploration of moral life as a legitimate topic of philosophical investigation. In contrast to the predominant focus on action and decision, she argues that “what we require is a renewed sense of the difficulty and complexity of the moral life and the opacity of persons. We need more concepts in terms of which to picture the substance of our being” (AD 293).1 I shall argue that to fully appreciate the n…Read more
  •  123
    Rawls on the Objectivity of Practical Reason
    Croatian Journal of Philosophy 1 (3): 307-329. 2001.
    This article argues that Rawls’ history of ethics importantly contributes to the advancement of ethical theory, in that it correctly situates Kantian constructivism as an alternative to both sentimentalism and rational Intuitionism, and calls attention to the standards of objectivity in ethics. The author shows that by suggesting that both Intuitionist and Humean doctrines face the charge of heteronomy, Rawls appearsto adopt a Kantian conception of practical reason. Furthermore, Rawls follows Ka…Read more
  •  256
    Respect and Membership in the Moral Community
    Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 10 (2). 2007.
    Some philosophers object that Kant's respect cannot express mutual recognition because it is an attitude owed to persons in virtue of an abstract notion of autonomy and invite us to integrate the vocabulary of respect with other persons-concepts or to replace it with a social conception of recognition. This paper argues for a dialogical interpretation of respect as the key-mode of recognition of membership in the moral community. This interpretation highlights the relational and practical nature…Read more
  •  23
    Premessa
    Iride: Filosofia e Discussione Pubblica 20 (1): 63-66. 2007.
  •  10
    In symmetrical moral dilemmas, the agent faces a choice between two incompatible actions, which are equally justified on the basis of the same value. These cases are generally discounted as spurious or irrelevant on the assumption that, when there is no failure of commensurability, choice between symmetrical requirements is indifferent and can be determined by randomization. Alternatively, this article argues that the appeal to randomization allows the agent to overcome a deliberative impasse, b…Read more
  •  129
    The appeal of Kantian intuitionism
    European Journal of Philosophy 17 (1): 152-158. 2009.
    No Abstract
  •  19
    Review of Charles Larmore The Autonomy of Morality (review)
    Philosophical Review 118 (4): 536-540. 2009.