•  132
    Counter Thought Experiments
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 61 155-177. 2007.
    Let's begin with an old example. In De Rerum Naturua , Lucretius presented a thought experiment to show that space is infinite. We imagine ourselves near the alleged edge of space; we throw a spear; we see it either sail through the ‘edge’ or we see it bounce back. In the former case the ‘edge’ isn't the edge, after all. In the latter case, there must be something beyond the ‘edge’ that repelled the spear. Either way, the ‘edge’ isn't really an edge of space, after all. So space is infinite
  •  11
    Book Review:Science and Convention Jerzy Giedymin (review)
    Philosophy of Science 52 (1): 168-. 1985.
  •  13
    Book review The Science Wars (review)
    Philosophy of Science 72 (3): 523-525. 2005.
  •  80
    Money, Method and Medical Research
    Episteme 1 (1): 49-59. 2004.
    It's sometimes useful to start with a quiz, even if it seems irrelevant to the issues at hand. Suppose you have to organize a tennis tournament with, say, 1025 players. Match winners will go on to the next round while losers bow out until all have been eliminated except, of course, the final champion. Your problem is this: How many matches must you book for this tournament?
  • A defence of a priori knowledge of nature via thought experiments. The article is part of a pair, the counter-view argued by John Norton.
  •  23
    Boundaries, Reasons, and Ideology: Reply to Sismondo
    Episteme 1 (3): 249-255. 2005.
    Sergio Sismondo's “Boundary Work and the Science Wars” nicely exemplifies a hotly debated central issue. One side, let me call them the rationalists, tries to explain episodes in the history of science in terms of reason. They claim that scientists, past and present, believe what they do because of the evidence that they have at the time. The other side, following Sismondo, let me call them STSers , claim that social and other non-cognitive factors are the frequent causes of belief. This disagre…Read more
  •  105
    Politics, method, and medical research
    Philosophy of Science 75 (5): 756-766. 2008.
    There is sufficient evidence that intellectual property rights are corrupting medical research. One could respond to this from a moral or from an epistemic point of view. I take the latter route. Often in the sciences factual discoveries lead to new methodological norms. Medical research is an example. Surprisingly, the methodological change required will involve political change. Instead of new regulations aimed at controlling the problem, the outright socialization of research seems called for…Read more
  •  15
    Introduction to the special issue on rationality
    International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 13 (3): 213. 1999.
    No abstract
  •  8
    “Dubrovnik”
    International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 13 (2): 101. 1999.
    No abstract
  •  129
    Thought experiments since the scientific revolution
    International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 1 (1). 1986.
    No abstract
  •  31
    Proof and truth in Lakatos's masterpiece
    International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 4 (2). 1990.
    Abstract Proofs and Refutations is Lakatos's masterpiece. This article investigates some of its central themes, in particular: the nature of proofs ('Proofs do not prove, they improve'); the nature of definitions (real, not nominal); and the consequences of all this for ontology (platonism vs Popper's World Three)
  •  99
    Funding, objectivity and the socialization of medical research
    Science and Engineering Ethics 8 (3): 295--308. 2002.
    There has been a sharp rise in private funding of medical research, especially in relation to patentable products. Several serious problems with this are described. A solution involving the elimination of patents and public funding administered through extended national health care systems is proposed.
  •  75
    Review of Alexander Bird's book Thomas Kuhn (review)
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 53 (1): 143-149. 2002.
  •  226
    Proofs and pictures
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 48 (2): 161-180. 1997.
    Everyone appreciates a clever mathematical picture, but the prevailing attitude is one of scepticism: diagrams, illustrations, and pictures prove nothing; they are psychologically important and heuristically useful, but only a traditional verbal/symbolic proof provides genuine evidence for a purported theorem. Like some other recent writers (Barwise and Etchemendy [1991]; Shin [1994]; and Giaquinto [1994]) I take a different view and argue, from historical considerations and some striking exampl…Read more
  •  2
    Editorial
    International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 15 (2). 2001.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  159
    Peeking into Plato’s Heaven
    Philosophy of Science 71 (5): 1126-1138. 2004.
    Examples of classic thought experiments are presented and some morals drawn. The views of my fellow symposiasts, Tamar Gendler, John Norton, and James McAllister, are evaluated. An account of thought experiments along a priori and Platonistic lines is given. I also cite the related example of proving theorems in mathematics with pictures and diagrams. To illustrate the power of these methods, a possible refutation of the continuum hypothesis using a thought experiment is sketched.
  •  14
    Philosophy of Science: The Key Thinkers (edited book)
    Continuum Books. 2012.
    From the 19th century the philosophy of science has been shaped by a group of influential figures. Who were they? Why do they matter? This introduction brings to life the most influential thinkers in the philosophy of science, uncovering how the field has developed over the last 200 years. Taking up the subject from the time when some philosophers began to think of themselves not just as philosophers but as philosophers of science, a team of leading contemporary philosophers explain, criticize a…Read more
  •  52
    The philosophy of mathematical practice
    International Journal of Philosophical Studies 18 (1). 2010.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  39
    Critical Notice of Roy Sorensen Thought Experiments
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 25 (1): 135-142. 1995.
    This book adds to the growing literature on thought experiments. There are numerous examples drawn from the sciences and philosophy. The principle claim is that thought experiments are a limiting case of real experiments. It is a moderate empiricist view, in contrast to, e.g., the Platonism of Brown or the strict empiricism of Norton. Highly recommended
  •  6
    Book reviews (review)
    with Joshua Mozersky, Rodney Watkins, and Andrew Reynolds
    International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 12 (1): 91-102. 1998.
    Time's Arrow and Archimedes’ Point: New Directions for the Physics of Time Huw PRICE, 1996 New York, Oxford University Press xiii + 306 pp. SCAN 37.00 ISBN 0–19–510095–6 Mental Reality GALEN STRAWSON, 1994 Cambridge, MA, The MIT Press xiv + 337 pp., S37.50, $17.50 ISBN 0–262–19352–3 The Rule of Reason: The Philosophy of Charles Sanders Peirce JACQUELINE BRUNNING & PAUL FORSTER, Eds, 1997 Toronto, University of Toronto Press 316 pp., $80.00, $24.95 ISBN 0–8020–0829–1, ISBN 0–8020–7819–2 Scientifi…Read more
  •  39
    Einstein's brand of verificationism
    International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 2 (1). 1987.
    (1987). Einstein's brand of verificationism. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science: Vol. 2, No. 1, pp. 33-54. doi: 10.1080/02698598708573301