•  55
    In one of the few widely discussed passages in the Doctrine of Right, Kant makes the surprising claim that a shipwrecked sailor who dislodges another from a plank that will support only one of them is "culpable, but not punishable." Many commentators regard this passage as a sort of smoking gun that shows that, in extremis, Kant resorts to the very sort of empirical and consequentialist reasoning that he claims to do without.2 My aim in this paper is to defend his analysis, by showing both that …Read more
  •  284
    In this masterful work, both an illumination of Kant's thought and an important contribution to contemporary legal and political theory, Arthur Ripstein gives a comprehensive yet accessible account of Kant's political philosophy. In addition to providing a clear and coherent statement of the most misunderstood of Kant's ideas, Ripstein also shows that Kant's views remain conceptually powerful and morally appealing today.
  •  41
    What Can Philosophy Teach Us About Multiculturalism? (review)
    Dialogue 36 (3): 607-614. 1997.
    Multiculturalism is an increasingly important topic for philosophers, largely because of the practical problems posed by diversity. Traditional political philosophy had little to say about cultural difference, taking the existence of a shared language and culture pretty much for granted. The multicultural societies of the contemporary world make such assumptions untenable. Traditional questions of fairness and sovereignty find hard cases in such policy issues as immigration, education, criminal …Read more
  •  63
    Critical notice
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 40 (4): 669-699. 2010.
    The 2008 meltdown in global capital markets has led to a renewed interest in questions of economic distribution. Many people suggest that the motives, incentive structures, and institutions in place were inadequate and, for the first time in a generation, public debate is animated by arguments about the need for greater equality. G.A. Cohen's new book resonates with many of the themes of these debates; he advocates a more thoroughgoing equality, even more thoroughgoing than that demanded by John…Read more
  •  1079
    Authority and Coercion
    Philosophy and Public Affairs 32 (1): 2-35. 2004.
    I am grateful to Donald Ainslie, Lisa Austin, Michael Blake, Abraham Drassinower, David Dyzenhaus, George Fletcher, Robert Gibbs, Louis-Philippe Hodgson, Sari Kisilevsky, Dennis Klimchuk, Christopher Morris, Scott Shapiro, Horacio Spector, Sergio Tenenbaum, Malcolm Thorburn, Ernest Weinrib, Karen Weisman, and the Editors of Philosophy & Public Affairs for comments, and audiences in the UCLA Philosophy Department and Columbia Law School for their questions.
  •  40
    Liberal Justification and the Limits of Neutrality
    Analyse & Kritik 14 (1): 3-17. 1992.
    This paper examines a style of political justification prominent in contemporary liberalism, according to which policies are legitimate only if they can be shown to be acceptable to all. Although this approach is often associated with neutrality about the good life, it is argued that liberalism cannot be neutral about questions of the role of various goods, such as work, play and community. The paper closes by exploring the implications and applicability of this account of justification to conte…Read more
  •  16
    Responses to Humiliation
    Social Research: An International Quarterly 64. 1997.
  •  1
    Rationality and Alienation
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supplementary Volume 15 (n/a): 449. 1989.
  •  22
    Gauthier's Liberal Individual
    Dialogue 28 (1): 63-. 1989.
  •  87
    Equality, Luck, and Responsibility
    Philosophy and Public Affairs 23 (1): 3-23. 1994.
  •  1
    Thomas Scanlon, What We Owe to Each Other (review)
    Philosophy in Review 20 62-65. 2000.
  •  256
    Beyond the Harm Principle
    Philosophy and Public Affairs 34 (3): 215-245. 2006.
  •  87
    In A Theory of Justice, Rawls makes almost no mention of the issues of justice that animated philosophers in earlier centuries. There is no discussion of justice between persons, issues that Aristotle sought to explain under the idea of “corrective justice.” Nor is there discussion, except in passing, of punishment, another primary focus of the social contract approaches of Locke, Rousseau and Kant.1 My aim in this article is to argue that implicit in Rawls’s writing is a powerful and persuasive…Read more
  •  36
    Strictly Speaking—It Went Without Saying
    with Brian Langille
    Legal Theory 2 (1): 63-81. 1996.
    Herbert Simon once observed that watching an ant make its way across the uneven surface of a beach, one can easily be impressed—too impressed—with the foresight and complexity of the ant's internal map of the beach. Simon went on to point out that such an attribution of complexity to the ant makes a serious mistake. Most of the complexity is not in the ant but in the beach. The ant is just complex enough to use the features of the beach to find its way.
  •  35
    Law and disagreement
    Philosophical Review 110 (4): 611-614. 2001.
    Author Jeremy Waldron has thoroughly revised thirteen of his most recent essays in order to offer a comprehensive critique of the idea of the judicial review of legislation. He argues that a belief in rights is not the same as a commitment to a Bill of Rights. This book presents legislation by a representative assembly as a form of law making which is especially apt for a society whose members disagree with one another about fundamental issues of principle
  •  25
    Reclaiming Proportionality
    Journal of Applied Philosophy 33 (3). 2016.
  •  99
    Justice and Responsibility
    Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 17 (2): 361-386. 2004.
    I argue that institutions charged with giving justice must understand responsibility in terms of norms governing what people are entitled to expect of each other. On this conception, the sort of responsibility that is of interest to private law or distributive justice is not a relation between a person and the consequence, but rather a relation between persons with respect to consequences. As a result, nonrelational facts about a person’s actions and the circumstances in which she performs them …Read more
  • Phl 370s Issues in the Philosophy of Law
    Custom Publishing Service, University of Toronto Bookstores. 1999.
  •  80
    Form and Matter in Kantian Political Philosophy: A Reply
    European Journal of Philosophy 20 (3): 487-496. 2012.
    This paper responds briefly to four reviews of Force and Freedom. Valentini and Sangiovanni criticize what they see as the excessive formalism of the Kantian enterprise, contending that the Kantian project is circular, because it defines rights and freedom together, and that this circularity renders it unable to say anything determinate about appropriate restrictions and permissions. I show that the appearance of circularity arises from a misconstrual of the Kantian idea of a right. Properly und…Read more
  •  162
    Critical notice too much invested to quit
    Economics and Philosophy 20 (1): 185-208. 2004.
    Faculty of Law and Department of Philosophy, University of Toronto 1. INTRODUCTION The economic analysis of law has gone through a remarkable change in the past decade and a half. The founding articles of the discipline – such classic pieces as Ronald Coase’s “The problem of social cost” (1960), Richard Posner’s “A theory of negligence” (1972) and Guido Calabresi and Douglas Malamed’s “Property rules, liability rules, and inalienability: One view of the cathedral” (1972) – offered economic analy…Read more
  •  33
    The Ideal Libertarian
    Dialogue 29 (2): 285-. 1990.