•  9
    Leibniz’s ‘New System’ and Associated Contemporary Texts (review)
    The Leibniz Review 8 100-104. 1998.
  •  140
    Essays on Descartes
    Philosophical Review 122 (1): 122-125. 2013.
  •  249
    Descartes's case for dualism
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 33 (1): 29-63. 1995.
    Descartes's dualism, and his argument for it, are often understood in terms of the modal notion of separability. I argue that the central notions, substance and real distinction, should not be understood this way. Descartes's well-known argument for dualism relies implicitly on views he spells out in the Principles of Philosophy, where he explains that a substance has a nature that consists in a single attribute, and all its qualities are modes of that nature. The argument relies ultimately on…Read more
  •  124
    The first meditation and the senses
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 4 (1). 1996.
    One question that has created controversy among interpreters is just how much is in doubt at the end of the Dream Argument in Meditation I. I argue that there is doubt about the existence of composite bodies not yet about the existence of a physical world. I also caution against using later parts of the Meditations to interpret the First Meditation on account of the order of reasons in this work. I connect the Omnipotent God argument to Descartes's views about innate ideas and analyze the Fir…Read more
  •  209
    Mills Can't Think: Leibniz's Approach to the Mind-Body Problem
    Res Philosophica 91 (1): 1-28. 2014.
    In the Monadology Leibniz has us imagine a thinking machine the size of a mill in order to show that matter can’t think. The argument is often thought to rely on the unity of consciousness and the notion of simplicity. Leibniz himself did not see matters this way. For him the argument relies on the view that the qualities of a substance must be intimately connected to its nature by being modifications, limitations of its nature. Leibniz thinks perception is not a modification of matter because i…Read more
  •  32
    Physiologia (review)
    Philosophical Review 107 (2): 330-332. 1998.
    In recent years more and more scholars of early modern philosophy have come to acknowledge that our understanding of Descartes’s thought benefits greatly from consideration of his intellectual background. Research in this direction has taken off, but much work remains to be done. Dennis Des Chene offers a major contribution to this enterprise. This erudite book is the result of a very impressive body of research into a number of late Aristotelian scholastics, some fairly well known, such as Suár…Read more
  •  18
  •  2
    I argue that Descartes's best known argument for dualism relies on claims about intellectual activity and not on claims about mental states generally to establish dualism. I explain that this must be so give his historical context, where arguments for the immateriality of the mind on the basis of the intellect were common. But sensation and other non-intellectual states were regarded as pertaining to the body-soul composite.
  •  8
    Descartes and the Immortality of the Soul
    In John Cottingham & Peter Hacker (eds.), Mind, Method and Morality: Essays in Honour of Anthony Kenny, Oxford University Press. 2010.
    Descartes held that the human mind or soul is indivisible, unlike body. In this paper I argue that his treatment of this feature of the soul is intimately connected to his engagement with Aristotelian scholasticism. I discuss two strands in Descartes. There is a long tradition of arguing for the immortality of the human soul on the basis of this view. Descartes did use this view in defense of dualism, but I argue that he held that the soul’s immortality should be established rather on the ba…Read more
  • Review (review)
    Theoria 72 (1): 91-95. 2006.
  •  2
    Leibniz on final causation
    In Samuel Newlands & Larry M. Jorgensen (eds.), Metaphysics and the good: themes from the philosophy of Robert Merrihew Adams, Oxford University Press. 2009.
    Early modern philosophers rejected various important aspects of Aristotelianism. Current scholarship debates the question to what extent the early moderns rejected final causation. Leibniz explicitly endorsed it. I argue that his notion of final causation should be understood in connection with his resurrection of substantial forms and his seeing such forms on the model of the soul. I relate Leibniz’ conception of final causation to the Aristotelian background as well as Descartes’s treatm…Read more
  •  88
    Evans on de re thought
    Philosophia 22 (3-4): 275-298. 1993.
  •  223
    Descartes's Changing Mind (review)
    Philosophical Review 121 (1): 137-139. 2012.