Cornell University
Sage School of Philosophy
PhD, 1977
CV
Charlottesville, Virginia, United States of America
Areas of Interest
History of Western Philosophy
  •  509
    Philosophical anarchism
    In Social Science Research Network, Cambridge University Press. 2001.
    Anarchist political philosophers normally include in their theories (or implicitly rely upon) a vision of a social life very different than the life experienced by most persons today. Theirs is a vision of autonomous, noncoercive, productive interaction among equals, liberated from and without need for distinctively political institutions, such as formal legal systems or governments or the state. This "positive" part of anarchist theories, this vision of the good social life, will be discussed o…Read more
  •  17
  •  35
  •  248
    The anarchist position: A reply to Klosko and Senor
    Philosophy and Public Affairs 16 (3): 269-279. 1987.
  •  40
    Boundaries of Authority
    Oxford University Press USA. 2016.
    Modern states claim rights of jurisdiction and control over particular geographical areas and their associated natural resources. Boundaries of Authority explores the possible moral bases for such territorial claims by states, in the process arguing that many of these territorial claims in fact lack any moral justification. The book maintains throughout that the requirement of states' justified authority over persons has normative priority over, and as a result severely restricts, the kinds of t…Read more
  •  29
    The prelims comprise: The Basic Concepts The Philosophical Problem Brief History Socrates and the Three Strategies Particularity and Natural Duty Accounts Associative Accounts Transactional Accounts Pluralist and Anarchist Responses Bibliography.
  •  86
    Original-Acquisition Justifications of Private Property
    Social Philosophy and Policy 11 (2): 63-84. 1994.
    My aim in this essay is to explore the nature and force of “original-acquisition” justifications of private property. By “original-acquisition” justifications, I mean those arguments which purport to establish or importantly contribute to the moral defense of private property by: offering a moral/historical account of how legitimate private property rights for persons first arose ; offering a hypothetical or conjectural account of how justified private property could arise from a propertyless co…Read more
  •  521
    Justification and legitimacy
    Ethics 109 (4): 739-771. 1999.
    In this essay I will discuss the relationship between two of the most basic ideas in political and legal philosophy: the justification of the state and state legitimacy. I plainly cannot aspire here to a complete account of these matters; but I hope to be able to say enough to motivate a way of thinking about the relation between these notions that is, I believe, superior to the approach which seems to be dominant in contemporary political philosophy. Today showing that a state is justified and …Read more
  •  309
    The principle of fair play
    Philosophy and Public Affairs 8 (4): 307-337. 1979.
  •  25
    Democracy’s Discontent (review)
    Philosophical Review 107 (1): 133-135. 1998.
    As its subtitle indicates, Democracy’s Discontent is a study of the political philosophies that have guided America’s public life. The “search” Michael Sandel describes has, in his view, temporarily come to a disappointing resolution in America’s acceptance of a liberal “public philosophy” that “cannot secure the liberty it promises” and has left Americans “discontented” with their “loss of self-government and the erosion of community”. This theme is unlikely to surprise readers familiar with Sa…Read more
  •  48
    Reasonable expectations and obligations: A reply to Postow
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 19 (1): 123-127. 1981.
  •  40
    Moral Principles and Political Obligations
    Philosophical Review 90 (3): 472. 1981.
  •  23
    Punishment: A Philosophy and Public Affairs Reader (edited book)
    with Marshall Cohen, Joshua Cohen, and Charles R. Beitz
    Princeton University Press. 1994.
    The problem of justifying legal punishment has been at the heart of legal and social philosophy from the very earliest recorded philosophical texts. However, despite several hundred years of debate, philosophers have not reached agreement about how legal punishment can be morally justified. That is the central issue addressed by the contributors to this volume. All of the essays collected here have been published in the highly respected journal Philosophy & Public Affairs. Taken together, they o…Read more
  •  2
    Moral Principles and Political Obligations
    Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 87 (4): 568-568. 1980.
  •  82
    Historical rights and fair shares
    Law and Philosophy 14 (2). 1995.
    My aim of this paper is to clarify, and in a certain very limited way to defend, historical theories of property rights (and their associated theories of social or distributive justice). It is important, I think, to better understand historical rights for several reasons: first, because of the extent to which historical theories capture commonsense, unphilosophical views about property and justice; then, because historical theories have fallen out of philosophical fashion, and are consequently n…Read more
  •  561
    Tacit consent and political obligation
    Philosophy and Public Affairs 5 (3): 274-291. 1976.
  •  196
    Consent theory for libertarians
    Social Philosophy and Policy 22 (1): 330-356. 2005.
    This paper argues that libertarian political philosophers, including Robert Nozick, have erred in neglecting the problem of political obligation and that they ought to embrace an actual consent theory of political obligation and state legitimacy. It argues as well that if they followed this recommendation, their position on the subject would be correct. I identify the tension in libertarian (and especially Nozick's) thought between its minimalist and its consensualist strains and argue that, on …Read more