Cornell University
Sage School of Philosophy
PhD, 1977
CV
Charlottesville, Virginia, United States of America
Areas of Interest
History of Western Philosophy
  •  124
    External justifications and institutional roles
    Journal of Philosophy 93 (1): 28-36. 1996.
    In his paper "Role Obligations," Michael Hardimon defends an account of the nature and justification of institutional obligations that he takes to be clearly superior to the "standard" voluntarist view. Hardimon argues that this standard view presents a "misleading and distorted" picture of role obligations (and of morality generally); and in its best form he claims this view still "leaves out" of its understanding of even contractual role obligations an "absolutely vital factor". I argue agains…Read more
  •  224
    Is There a Duty to Obey the Law?
    Cambridge University Press. 2005.
    The central question in political philosophy is whether political states have the right to coerce their constituents and whether citizens have a moral duty to obey the commands of their state. In this 2005 book, Christopher Heath Wellman and A. John Simmons defend opposing answers to this question. Wellman bases his argument on samaritan obligations to perform easy rescues, arguing that each of us has a moral duty to obey the law as his or her fair share of the communal samaritan chore of rescui…Read more
  •  8
    Bentham
    Philosophical Review 87 (4): 610. 1978.
  •  18
    Social Justice
    Philosophical Review 86 (4): 590. 1977.
  •  97
    Makers' rights
    The Journal of Ethics 2 (3): 197-218. 1998.
    This paper examines the thesis that human labor creates property rights in or from previously unowned objects by virtue of labor's power to make new things. This thesis is considered for two possible roles: first, as a thesis to which John Locke might have been committed in his writings on property; and second, as a thesis of independent plausibility that could serve as part of a defensible contemporary theory of property rights. Understanding Locke as committed to the thesis of makers' rights h…Read more
  •  102
    Inalienable rights and Locke's treatises
    Philosophy and Public Affairs 12 (3): 175-204. 1983.
  •  139
    Democratic Authority and the Boundary Problem
    Ratio Juris 26 (3): 326-357. 2013.
    Theories of political authority divide naturally into those that locate the source of states' authority in the history of states' interactions with their subjects and those that locate it in structural (or functional) features of states (such as the justice of their basic institutions). This paper argues that purely structuralist theories of political authority (such as those defended by Kant, Rawls, and contemporary “democratic Kantians”) must fail because of their inability to solve the bounda…Read more
  •  72
    The Lockean Theory of Rights
    Princeton University Press. 2020.
    John Locke's political theory has been the subject of many detailed treatments by philosophers and political scientists. But The Lockean Theory of Rights is the first systematic, full-length study of Locke's theory of rights and of its potential for making genuine contributions to contemporary debates about rights and their place in political philosophy. Given that the rights of persons are the central moral concept at work in Locke's and Lockean political philosophy, such a study is long overdu…Read more
  •  55
    On the Edge of Anarchy: Locke, Consent, and the Limits of Society
    Philosophical Review 106 (1): 139. 1997.
    In On the Edge of Anarchy, A. John Simmons simultaneously pursues two distinguishable ends: to defend an interpretation of Locke as a “pure consent” theorist the essence of whose theory is that only actual voluntary individual consent can ground political obligations and authority, and to defend pure consent theory as the best theory of political obligation. Both ends are pursued under the heading of justifying “Lockean” consent theory, and the arguments for them overlap considerably because mos…Read more
  •  27
    Right and Wrong
    Philosophical Review 90 (1): 125. 1981.
  •  516
    Philosophical anarchism
    In Social Science Research Network, Cambridge University Press. 2001.
    Anarchist political philosophers normally include in their theories (or implicitly rely upon) a vision of a social life very different than the life experienced by most persons today. Theirs is a vision of autonomous, noncoercive, productive interaction among equals, liberated from and without need for distinctively political institutions, such as formal legal systems or governments or the state. This "positive" part of anarchist theories, this vision of the good social life, will be discussed o…Read more
  •  17
  •  36
  •  40
    Boundaries of Authority
    Oxford University Press USA. 2016.
    Modern states claim rights of jurisdiction and control over particular geographical areas and their associated natural resources. Boundaries of Authority explores the possible moral bases for such territorial claims by states, in the process arguing that many of these territorial claims in fact lack any moral justification. The book maintains throughout that the requirement of states' justified authority over persons has normative priority over, and as a result severely restricts, the kinds of t…Read more
  •  260
    The anarchist position: A reply to Klosko and Senor
    Philosophy and Public Affairs 16 (3): 269-279. 1987.
  •  31
    The prelims comprise: The Basic Concepts The Philosophical Problem Brief History Socrates and the Three Strategies Particularity and Natural Duty Accounts Associative Accounts Transactional Accounts Pluralist and Anarchist Responses Bibliography.