Madison, Wisconsin, United States of America
  •  121
    Sympathy, commitment, and preference
    Economics and Philosophy 21 (1): 33-50. 2005.
    While very much in Sen's camp in rejecting revealed preference theory and emphasizing the complexity, incompleteness, and context dependence of preference and the intellectual costs of supposing that all the factors influencing choice can be captured by a single notion of preference, this essay contests his view that economists should recognize multiple notions of preference. It argues that Sen's concerns are better served by embracing a single conception of preference and insisting on the need …Read more
  •  118
    Is an Overdose of Paracetamol Bad for One’s Health?
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 62 (3): 657-668. 2011.
    1 Overview of the problem2 Situationally Specific Normal Functioning and Capacities3 Kingma’s Criticism4 How Normal Responses can be Pathological5 Too Many Pathologies?6 Conclusions
  •  116
    Health, Naturalism, and Functional Efficiency
    Philosophy of Science 79 (4): 519-541. 2012.
    This essay develops an account of health, the functional efficiency theory, which derives from Christopher Boorse's biostatistical theory. Like the BST, the functional efficiency theory is a nonevaluative view of health, but unlike the BST, it argues that the fundamental theoretical task is to distinguish levels of efficiency with which the parts and processes within organisms and within systems within organisms function. Which of these to label as healthy or pathological is of secondary importa…Read more
  •  116
    Group risks, risks to groups, and group engagement in genetics research
    Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 17 (4): 351-369. 2007.
    : This essay distinguishes between two kinds of group harms: harms to individuals in virtue of their membership in groups and harms to "structured" groups that have a continuing existence, an organization, and interests of their own. Genetic research creates risks of causing both kinds of group harms, and engagement with the groups at risk can help to mitigate those harms. The two kinds of group harms call for different kinds of group engagement
  •  115
    Manipulation and the causal Markov condition
    Philosophy of Science 71 (5): 846-856. 2004.
    This paper explores the relationship between a manipulability conception of causation and the causal Markov condition (CM). We argue that violations of CM also violate widely shared expectations—implicit in the manipulability conception—having to do with the absence of spontaneous correlations. They also violate expectations concerning the connection between independence or dependence relationships in the presence and absence of interventions.
  •  110
    The Philosophy of Economics: An Anthology (edited book)
    Cambridge University Press. 1984.
    An anthology of works on the philosophy of economics, including classic texts and essays exploring specific branches and schools of economics. Completely revamped, this edition contains new selections, a revised introduction and a bibliography. The volume contains 26 chapters organized into five parts: Classic Discussions, Positivist and Popperian Views, Ideology and Normative Economics, Branches and Schools of Economics and Their Methodological Problems and New Directions in Economic Methodolog…Read more
  •  107
    Philosophy of economics: past and future
    Journal of Economic Methodology 28 (1): 14-22. 2021.
    This essay offers a history of the development of philosophy of economics from the 1830s until today, with a personal perspective on the developments of the last four decades. It argues that change...
  •  99
    Benevolence, justice, well-being and the health gradient
    Public Health Ethics 2 (3): 235-243. 2009.
    The health gradient among those who are by historical standards both remarkably healthy and well-off is of considerable moral importance with respect to benevolence, justice and the theory of welfare. Indeed it may help us to realize that for most people the good life lies in close and intricate social ties with others which can flourish only when inequalities are limited. The health gradient suggests that there is a story to be told in which egalitarian justice, solidarity, health and well-bein…Read more
  •  96
  •  91
    Weighing Lives
    Mind 114 (455): 718-722. 2005.
  •  88
    Why don't effects explain their causes?
    Synthese 94 (2). 1993.
  •  83
    an unpublished paper written in 1998-1999.
  •  81
    Causal priority
    Noûs 18 (2): 261-279. 1984.
  •  80
    Valuing Health
    Philosophy and Public Affairs 34 (3): 246-274. 2006.
  •  78
    Ceteris Paribus Clauses and Causality in Economics
    PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1988. 1988.
    In this paper I distinguish the kind of ceteris paribus qualifications that often attach to derivative generalizations from those which typically attach to fundamental laws and argue that the latter are typically more tractable. I provide a sketch of a semantics for qualified generalizations and an account of how they may be justified. In addition I argue that legitimate uses of ceteris paribus qualifications must satisfy specific causal conditions.
  •  77
    Behavioural economics and paternalism
    Economics and Philosophy 34 (1): 53-66. 2018.
    :Contemporary behavioural economics has documented common failures of reasoning that apparently make possible policies that benefit individuals by contravening or correcting their judgements. These policies appear to be paternalistic, even though a traditional view would deny that they are paternalistic on the grounds that policies such as nudges do not restrict individual liberty. It appears to many that a new definition of paternalism that takes its cue from behavioural economics is needed. Fu…Read more
  •  75
    Consequentialism and Preference Formation in Economics and Game Theory
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 59 111-130. 2006.
    When students first study expected utility, they are inclined to interpret it as a theory that explains preferences for lotteries in terms of preferences for outcomes. Knowing U($100) and U($0), the agent can calculate that the utility of a gamble of $100 on a fair coin coming up heads is U($100)/2 + U($0)/2. Utilities are indices representing preferences, so in calculating the utility of the gamble, one is apparently giving a causal explanation for the agent’s preference for the gamble.
  •  75
    People have thought about economics for as long as they have thought about how to manage their households, and indeed Aristotle assimilated the study of the economic affairs of a city to the study of the management of a household. During the two millennia between Aristotle and Adam Smith, one finds reflections concerning economic problems mainly in the context of discussions of moral or policy questions. For example, scholastic philosophers commented on money and interest in inquiries concerning…Read more
  •  72
    Health Inequalities and Why They Matter
    with Yukiko Asada and Thomas Hedemann
    Health Care Analysis 10 (2): 177-191. 2002.
    Health inequalities are of concern both becausestudying them may help one learn how to improvehealth and because health inequalities may beunjust. This paper argues that attending tothese reasons why health inequalities may beimportant undercuts the claims of researchersat the World Health Organization in favor offocusing on individual health variation ratherthan on social group health differences. Inequalities in individual health are of littleinterest unless one goes on to study how theyare re…Read more
  •  72
    The Inexact and Separate Science of Economics
    Cambridge University Press. 1992.
    This book offers a comprehensive overview of the structure, strategy and methods of assessment of orthodox theoretical economics. In Part I Professor Hausman explains how economists theorise, emphasising the essential underlying commitment of economists to a vision of economics as a separate science. In Part II he defends the view that the basic axioms of economics are 'inexact' since they deal only with the 'major' causes; unlike most writers on economic methodology, the author argues that it i…Read more
  •  71
    Essays on Philosophy and Economic Methodology
    Cambridge University Press. 1992.
    This collection brings together the essays of one of the foremost American philosophers of economics. Cumulatively they offer fresh perspectives on foundational questions such as: what sort of science is economics? and how successful can economists be in acquiring knowledge of their subject matter?
  •  69
    Many questions concerning health involve values. How well is a health system performing? How should resources be allocated between the health system and other uses or among competing healthrelated uses? How should the costs of health services be distributed among members of a population? Who among those in need of transplants should receive scarce organs? What is the best way to treat particular patients? Although many kinds of expertise bear on these questions, values play a large role in answe…Read more
  •  66
    Confirming mainstream economic theory
    Theoria 13 (2): 261-278. 1998.
    This essay is concerned with the special difficulties that arise in testing and appraising mainstream economic theory. I argue that, like other theories designed to apply to complex open systems, it is very hard to confirm mainsteam economics. Parts can be tested and appraised, but the theory is only very weakly supported by evidence