Madison, Wisconsin, United States of America
  •  78
    Ceteris Paribus Clauses and Causality in Economics
    PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1988. 1988.
    In this paper I distinguish the kind of ceteris paribus qualifications that often attach to derivative generalizations from those which typically attach to fundamental laws and argue that the latter are typically more tractable. I provide a sketch of a semantics for qualified generalizations and an account of how they may be justified. In addition I argue that legitimate uses of ceteris paribus qualifications must satisfy specific causal conditions.
  •  60
    Much ado about models
    Journal of Economic Methodology 22 (2): 241-246. 2015.
  •  38
    Rational Choice and Social Theory: A Comment
    Journal of Philosophy 92 (2): 96-102. 1995.
  •  39
    Causation and Experimentation
    American Philosophical Quarterly 23 (2). 1986.
  •  49
    Is utilitarianism useless?
    Theory and Decision 30 (3): 273-278. 1991.
  • Book Review (review)
    Economics and Philosophy 15 (2): 289-295. 1999.
  •  87
    Why don't effects explain their causes?
    Synthese 94 (2). 1993.
  •  96
    Group risks, risks to groups, and group engagement in genetics research
    Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 17 (4): 351-369. 2007.
    : This essay distinguishes between two kinds of group harms: harms to individuals in virtue of their membership in groups and harms to "structured" groups that have a continuing existence, an organization, and interests of their own. Genetic research creates risks of causing both kinds of group harms, and engagement with the groups at risk can help to mitigate those harms. The two kinds of group harms call for different kinds of group engagement
  •  30
    Preference, Value, Choice, and Welfare
    Cambridge University Press. 2011.
    This book is about preferences, principally as they figure in economics. It also explores their uses in everyday language and action, how they are understood in psychology and how they figure in philosophical reflection on action and morality. The book clarifies and for the most part defends the way in which economists invoke preferences to explain, predict and assess behavior and outcomes. Hausman argues, however, that the predictions and explanations economists offer rely on theories of prefer…Read more
  •  201
    Are markets morally free zones?
    Philosophy and Public Affairs 18 (4): 317-333. 1989.
    Markets are central institutions in societies such as ours, and it seems appropriate to ask whether markets treat individuals justly or unjustly and whether choices individuals make concerning their market behavior are just or unjust. After all, markets influence most important features of our lives from the environment in which we live to the ways in which we find pleasure and fulfillment. Within market life we collectively determine the shape of human existence.<1>.
  •  75
    People have thought about economics for as long as they have thought about how to manage their households, and indeed Aristotle assimilated the study of the economic affairs of a city to the study of the management of a household. During the two millennia between Aristotle and Adam Smith, one finds reflections concerning economic problems mainly in the context of discussions of moral or policy questions. For example, scholastic philosophers commented on money and interest in inquiries concerning…Read more
  •  36
    The Composition of Economic Causes
    The Monist 78 (3): 295-307. 1995.
    Discusses the composition of economic causes. Applications of John Stuart Mill’s inductive method to economics; Problems with the deductive method; Effect of multiple causal factors in economics; Derivation of economic laws; Mill’s arguments for deductive economics.
  • Defending Microeconomic Theory
    Philosophical Forum 15 (4): 392. 1984.
  • No Title available: Reviews
    Economics and Philosophy 15 (2): 289-295. 1999.
  •  182
    Revealed preference, belief, and game theory
    Economics and Philosophy 16 (1): 99-115. 2000.
    The notion of ‘revealed preference’ is unclear and should be abandoned. Defenders of the theory of revealed preference have misinterpreted legitimate concerns about the testability of economics as the demand that economists eschew reference to (unobservable) subjective states. As attempts to apply revealed-preference theory to game theory illustrate with particular vividness, this demand is mistaken.
  •  70
    Causal priority
    Noûs 18 (2): 261-279. 1984.
  •  29
    Rationality and Knavery
    Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook 5 67-79. 1998.
    This paper makes a modest point. Suppose one wants to evaluate alternative policies, institutions or even constitutions on the basis of their consequences. To do so, one needs to evaluate their consequences and one needs to know what their consequences are. Let us suppose that the role of economic theories and game theory in particular is mainly to help us to use information we already possess or that we can acquire at a reasonable cost to judge what the consequences will be. We do not necessari…Read more
  •  1
    Causal Asymmetries
    Mind 109 (436): 933-937. 2000.
  •  56
    Making Interpersonal Comparisons Coherently
    with Martin Barrett
    Economics and Philosophy 6 (2): 293. 1990.
    Many ethical theories, including in particular consequentialist moral the ories, require comparisons of the amount of good possessed or received by different people. In the case of some goods, such as monetary income, wealth, education, or health, such comparisons are relatively unproblematic. Even in the case of such goods there may be serious empirical measurement problems, but there appear to be no difficulties in principle. Thus Cooter and Rappoport maintained that there was no serious diffi…Read more
  •  113
    Health, Naturalism, and Functional Efficiency
    Philosophy of Science 79 (4): 519-541. 2012.
    This essay develops an account of health, the functional efficiency theory, which derives from Christopher Boorse's biostatistical theory. Like the BST, the functional efficiency theory is a nonevaluative view of health, but unlike the BST, it argues that the fundamental theoretical task is to distinguish levels of efficiency with which the parts and processes within organisms and within systems within organisms function. Which of these to label as healthy or pathological is of secondary importa…Read more
  •  99
    Benevolence, justice, well-being and the health gradient
    Public Health Ethics 2 (3): 235-243. 2009.
    The health gradient among those who are by historical standards both remarkably healthy and well-off is of considerable moral importance with respect to benevolence, justice and the theory of welfare. Indeed it may help us to realize that for most people the good life lies in close and intricate social ties with others which can flourish only when inequalities are limited. The health gradient suggests that there is a story to be told in which egalitarian justice, solidarity, health and well-bein…Read more
  •  165
    Equality versus priority: A misleading distinction
    Economics and Philosophy 31 (2): 229-238. 2015.
    People condemn inequalities for many reasons. For example, many who have no concern with distribution per se criticize inequalities in health care, because these inequalities lessen the benefits provided by the resources that are devoted to health care. Others who place no intrinsic value on distribution believe that a just society must show a special concern for those who are worst off. Some people, on the other hand, do place an intrinsic value on equality of distribution, regardless of its co…Read more
  •  38
    The Deductive Method
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy 15 (1): 372-388. 1990.
  •  63
    No doubt men are capable even now of much more unselfish service than they generally render; and the supreme aim of the economist is to discover how this latent social asset can be developed more quickly and turned to account more wisely. (Alfred Marshall, Principles of Economics , p. 8).
  •  51
    Economics as Separate and Inexact
    Economics and Philosophy 12 (2): 207-220. 1996.
    The Inexact and Separate Science of Economics offers an overview of standard microeconomics and general equilibrium theory. These are not the whole of orthodox economics, and orthodox economics is not the whole of economics. But orthodox economics dominates the profession, and the theoretical core of microeconomics and general equilibrium theory – what I called ‘equilibrium theory’ – is central to most orthodox economics. Unlike many methodological works, which focus almost exclusively on the em…Read more