Madison, Wisconsin, United States of America
  • No Title available: Reviews
    Economics and Philosophy 15 (2): 289-295. 1999.
  •  188
    Revealed preference, belief, and game theory
    Economics and Philosophy 16 (1): 99-115. 2000.
    The notion of ‘revealed preference’ is unclear and should be abandoned. Defenders of the theory of revealed preference have misinterpreted legitimate concerns about the testability of economics as the demand that economists eschew reference to (unobservable) subjective states. As attempts to apply revealed-preference theory to game theory illustrate with particular vividness, this demand is mistaken.
  •  81
    Causal priority
    Noûs 18 (2): 261-279. 1984.
  •  29
    Rationality and Knavery
    Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook 5 67-79. 1998.
    This paper makes a modest point. Suppose one wants to evaluate alternative policies, institutions or even constitutions on the basis of their consequences. To do so, one needs to evaluate their consequences and one needs to know what their consequences are. Let us suppose that the role of economic theories and game theory in particular is mainly to help us to use information we already possess or that we can acquire at a reasonable cost to judge what the consequences will be. We do not necessari…Read more
  •  1
    Causal Asymmetries
    Mind 109 (436): 933-937. 2000.
  •  56
    Making Interpersonal Comparisons Coherently
    with Martin Barrett
    Economics and Philosophy 6 (2): 293. 1990.
    Many ethical theories, including in particular consequentialist moral the ories, require comparisons of the amount of good possessed or received by different people. In the case of some goods, such as monetary income, wealth, education, or health, such comparisons are relatively unproblematic. Even in the case of such goods there may be serious empirical measurement problems, but there appear to be no difficulties in principle. Thus Cooter and Rappoport maintained that there was no serious diffi…Read more
  •  116
    Health, Naturalism, and Functional Efficiency
    Philosophy of Science 79 (4): 519-541. 2012.
    This essay develops an account of health, the functional efficiency theory, which derives from Christopher Boorse's biostatistical theory. Like the BST, the functional efficiency theory is a nonevaluative view of health, but unlike the BST, it argues that the fundamental theoretical task is to distinguish levels of efficiency with which the parts and processes within organisms and within systems within organisms function. Which of these to label as healthy or pathological is of secondary importa…Read more
  •  99
    Benevolence, justice, well-being and the health gradient
    Public Health Ethics 2 (3): 235-243. 2009.
    The health gradient among those who are by historical standards both remarkably healthy and well-off is of considerable moral importance with respect to benevolence, justice and the theory of welfare. Indeed it may help us to realize that for most people the good life lies in close and intricate social ties with others which can flourish only when inequalities are limited. The health gradient suggests that there is a story to be told in which egalitarian justice, solidarity, health and well-bein…Read more
  •  165
    Equality versus priority: A misleading distinction
    Economics and Philosophy 31 (2): 229-238. 2015.
    People condemn inequalities for many reasons. For example, many who have no concern with distribution per se criticize inequalities in health care, because these inequalities lessen the benefits provided by the resources that are devoted to health care. Others who place no intrinsic value on distribution believe that a just society must show a special concern for those who are worst off. Some people, on the other hand, do place an intrinsic value on equality of distribution, regardless of its co…Read more
  •  40
    The Deductive Method
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy 15 (1): 372-388. 1990.
  •  63
    No doubt men are capable even now of much more unselfish service than they generally render; and the supreme aim of the economist is to discover how this latent social asset can be developed more quickly and turned to account more wisely. (Alfred Marshall, Principles of Economics , p. 8).
  •  64
    Economics as Separate and Inexact
    Economics and Philosophy 12 (2): 207-220. 1996.
    The Inexact and Separate Science of Economics offers an overview of standard microeconomics and general equilibrium theory. These are not the whole of orthodox economics, and orthodox economics is not the whole of economics. But orthodox economics dominates the profession, and the theoretical core of microeconomics and general equilibrium theory – what I called ‘equilibrium theory’ – is central to most orthodox economics. Unlike many methodological works, which focus almost exclusively on the em…Read more
  •  23
    Philosophy and Economic Methodology
    PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1984. 1984.
    This paper is concerned with the puzzling divorce that exists between writing on economic methodology and work by philosophers of science. After documenting the extent and nature of the separation and making some disparaging comments about the quality of much of the literature on economic methodology, this essay argues that the divorce results from the differences between the aims of philosophers of science, who are concerned to learn about knowledge acquisition in disciplines such as economics,…Read more
  •  60
    Critical studies / book reviews
    Philosophia Mathematica 11 (3): 354-358. 2003.
  •  115
    Manipulation and the causal Markov condition
    Philosophy of Science 71 (5): 846-856. 2004.
    This paper explores the relationship between a manipulability conception of causation and the causal Markov condition (CM). We argue that violations of CM also violate widely shared expectations—implicit in the manipulability conception—having to do with the absence of spontaneous correlations. They also violate expectations concerning the connection between independence or dependence relationships in the presence and absence of interventions.
  •  11
    Review of C. L. ten (ed.), Mill's on Liberty: A Critical Guide (review)
    Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2009 (6). 2009.
  •  63
    Causal and Explanatory Asymmetry
    PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1982 (Volume One: Contributed Papers). 1982.
    This paper asks why causal asymmetries should give rise to explanatory asymmetries. One way to give some rationale for the asymmetries of causal explanation is to adopt a pragmatic view of explanation and to stress the fact that causes can be used to manipulate their effects. This paper argues, however, that when one recognizes that causal asymmetry is fundamentally an asymmetry of "connectedness", one can see how causal asymmetry leads to an objective difference between explanations in terms of…Read more
  •  179
    John Stuart mill's philosophy of economics
    Philosophy of Science 48 (3): 363-385. 1981.
    John Stuart Mill regards economics as an inexact and separate science which employs a deductive method. This paper analyzes and restates Mill's views and considers whether they help one to understand philosophical peculiarities of contemporary microeconomic theory. The author concludes that it is philosophically enlightening to interpret microeconomics as an inexact and separate science, but that Mill's notion of a deductive method has only a little to contribute.
  •  164
    Problems with Realism in Economics
    Economics and Philosophy 14 (2): 185-213. 1998.
    This essay attempts to distinguish the pressing issues for economists and economic methodologists concerning realism in economics from those issues that are of comparatively slight importance. In particular I shall argue that issues concerning the goals of science are of considerable interest in economics, unlike issues concerning the evidence for claims about unobservables, which have comparatively little relevance. In making this argument, this essay raises doubts about the two programs in con…Read more
  •  12
    Book Review (review)
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 39 (1): 231-233. 2008.
  •  131
    When Jack and Jill Make a Deal*: DANIEL M. HAUSMAN
    Social Philosophy and Policy 9 (1): 95-113. 1992.
    In ordinary circumstances, human actions have a myriad of unintended and often unforeseen consequences for the lives of other people. Problems of pollution are serious examples, but spillovers and side effects are the rule, not the exception. Who knows what consequences this essay may have? This essay is concerned with the problems of justice created by spillovers. After characterizing such spillovers more precisely and relating the concept to the economist's notion of an externality, I shall th…Read more
  •  46
    Health and Functional Efficiency
    Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 39 (6): 634-647. 2014.
    This essay argues that what is central to Christopher Boorse’s biostatistical theory of disease as statistically subnormal part function (BST) are comparisons of the “functional efficiency” of parts and processes and that statistical considerations serve only to pick out a healthy level of functional efficiency. On this interpretation, the distinction between health and pathology is less important than comparisons of functional efficiency, which are entirely independent of statistical considerat…Read more
  •  1
    And Preference
    In Fabienne Peter (ed.), Rationality and Commitment, Oxford University Press, Usa. pp. 49. 2007.
  •  219
    Egalitarianism Reconsidered
    with Matt Sensat Waldren
    Journal of Moral Philosophy 8 (4): 567-586. 2011.
    This paper argues that egalitarian theories should be judged by the degree to which they meet four different challenges. Fundamentalist egalitarianism, which contends that certain inequalities are intrinsically bad or unjust regardless of their consequences, fails to meet these challenges. Building on discussions by T.M. Scanlon and David Miller, we argue that egalitarianism is better understood in terms of commitments to six egalitarian objectives. A consequence of our view, in contrast to Mart…Read more