•  77
    Attention and self in Buddhist philosophy of mind
    Ratio 31 (4): 354-362. 2018.
    Buddhist philosophy of mind is fascinating because it denies that there is a self in one of the ways that has traditionally seemed best able to make sense of that idea: the idea that the self is the agent of actions including the thinking of thoughts. In the Buddhist philosophy of mind of the fifth century thinker Buddhaghosa what does the explanatory work is instead attention. Attention replaces self in the explanation of cognition’s grounding in perception and action; it does this because it p…Read more
  •  14
    Mental Time Travel and Attention: Replies to Commentators
    Australasian Philosophical Review 1 (4): 450-455. 2017.
  •  59
    Mental Time Travel and Attention
    Australasian Philosophical Review 1 (4): 353-373. 2017.
    ABSTRACTEpisodic memory is the ability to revisit events in one's personal past, to relive them as if one travelled back in mental time. It has widely been assumed that such an ability imposes a metaphysical requirement on selves. Buddhist philosophers, however, deny the requirement and therefore seek to provide accounts of episodic memory that are metaphysically parsimonious. The idea that the memory perspective is a centred field of experience whose phenomenal constituents are simulacra of an …Read more
  •  107
    The debates between various Buddhist and Hindu philosophical systems about the existence, definition and nature of self, occupy a central place in the history of Indian philosophy and religion.
  •  1
  •  591
    Epistemology from a Sanskritic Point of View
    In Masaharu Mizumoto, Stephen P. Stich & Eric S. McCready (eds.), Epistemology for the Rest of the World, Oxford University Press. pp. 12-21. 2018.
  •  76
    What Is Philosophy?
    The Harvard Review of Philosophy 24 1-8. 2017.
    Three rival conceptions of philosophy overlap, we may imagine, in the Sassinid court of Chosroes (r. 531–579). One is due to Priscian, a refugee from Athens after Justinian’s closing of the philosophical schools. A second and third are from India: the Buddhist conception of Vasubandhu and the Nyāya view of Vātsyāyana. I will argue that the rivalry between these three understandings of philosophy ultimately rests in three different conceptions of what makes an inner life one’s own.
  •  64
  •  800
    Attention, Not Self
    Oxford University Press. 2017.
    Jonardon Ganeri presents a radically reoriented account of mind, to which attention is the key. It is attention, not self, that explains the experiential and normative situatedness of humans in the world. Ganeri draws together three disciplines: analytic philosophy and phenomenology, cognitive science and psychology, and Buddhist thought.
  •  106
    The Oxford Handbook of Indian Philosophy (edited book)
    Oxford University Press. 2014.
    The Oxford Handbook of Indian Philosophy tells the story of philosophy in India through a series of exceptional individual acts of philosophical virtuosity. It brings together forty leading international scholars to record the diverse figures, movements, and approaches that constitute philosophy in the geographical region of the Indian subcontinent, a region sometimes nowadays designated South Asia. The chapters provide a synopsis of the liveliest areas of contemporary research and set new agend…Read more
  •  19
    Reply to Jay Garfield
    Philosophical Quarterly 64 (255): 346-347. 2014.
  •  90
    Contextualism in the Study of Indian Intellectual Cultures
    Journal of Indian Philosophy 36 (5-6): 551-562. 2008.
    When J. L. Austin introduced two “shining new tools to crack the crib of reality”—the theory of performative utterances and the doctrine of infelicities—he could not have imagined that he was also about to inaugurate a shining new industry in the philosophy of the social sciences. But with its evident concern for the features to which “all acts are heir which have the general character of ritual or ceremonial,” Austin’s theory soon became indispensable in the analysis of ritual, linguistic and e…Read more
  •  751
    An Irrealist Theory of Self
    The Harvard Review of Philosophy 12 (1): 60-79. 2004.
    It has become a common-place to read the ‘no-self’ theory of the Buddhist philosophers as a reductionist account of persons. In Reasons and Persons, Derek Parfit himself seemed to endorse the association, having learned of the Buddhist theory from his colleague at All Souls College, Bimal Krishna Matilal. The Buddha’s denial that there are real selves metaphysically distinct from continuous streams of psycho-physical constituents lends itself, to be sure, to a reductionist interpretation. I beli…Read more
  •  16
    The last work of the eminent philosopher Bimal Krishna Matilal, this book traces the origins of logical theory in India.
  •  41
    Traditions of truth – changing beliefs and the nature of inquiry
    Journal of Indian Philosophy 33 (1): 43-54. 2005.
  •  13
    Epistemology in PracÄ«na and Navya Nyāya (review) (review)
    Philosophy East and West 57 (1): 120-123. 2007.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Epistemology in Pracīna and Navya NyāyaJonardon GaneriEpistemology in Pracīna and Navya Nyāya. By Sukharanjan Saha. Kolkata: Jadavpur University, 2003. Pp. 166.Epistemology in Pracīna and Navya Nyāya, by Sukharanjan Saha, usefully collates ten previously published essays on Indian epistemology: two longer essays first published in 1986 and a series of more recent shorter pieces. The leading thesis of the book is that the …Read more
  •  4067
    Indian logic
    In Dov M. Gabbay, John Woods & Akihiro Kanamori (eds.), Handbook of the History of Logic, Elsevier. pp. 1--309. 2004.
  •  22
    Cross-Modality and the Self
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 61 (3): 639-657. 2000.
    The thesis of this paper is that the capacity to think of one’s perceptions as cross-modally integrated is incompatible with a reductionist account of the self. In §2 I distinguish three versions of the argument from cross-modality. According to the ‘unification’ version of the argument, what needs to be explained is one’s capacity to identify an object touched as the same as an object simultaneously seen. According to the ‘recognition’ version, what needs to be explained is one’s capacity, havi…Read more
  •  14
    Philosophy as Therapeia (edited book)
    Cambridge University Press. 2010.
    'Empty are the words of that philosopher who offers therapy for no human suffering. For just as there is no use in medical expertise if it does not give therapy for bodily diseases, so too there is no use in philosophy if it does not expel the suffering of the soul.' The philosopher Epicurus gave famous voice to a conception of philosophy as a cure or remedy for the maladies of the human soul. What has not until now received attention is just how prominent an idea this has been across a whole sp…Read more
  • Vyadi and The Realist Theory of Meaning
    Journal of Indian Philosophy 23 (4): 403-428. 1995.
  •  764
    Emergentisms, Ancient and Modern
    Mind 120 (479): 671-703. 2011.
    Jaegwon Kim has argued (Kim 2006a) that the two key issues for emergentism are to give a positive characterization of the emergence relation and to explain the possibility of downward causation. This paper proposes an account of emergence which provides new answers to these two key issues. It is argued that an appropriate emergence relation is characterized by a notion of ‘transformation’, and that the real key issue for emergentism is located elsewhere than the places Kim identifies. The paper …Read more
  •  18
    Artha: Meaning
    Oxford University Press India. 2011.
    This book examines the theories of meaning or artha in different schools of philosophical thought highlighting the significant relationship between 'word' and 'meaning'. It demonstrates that classical Indian theory of language can inform and be informed by contemporary philosophy.
  •  28
    The Character of Logic in India
    with John A. Taber, Bimal Krishna Matilal, and Heeraman Tiwari
    Journal of the American Oriental Society 121 (4): 681. 2001.