University of Pittsburgh
Department of Philosophy
PhD, 1972
CV
New Haven, Connecticut, United States of America
  •  35
    The actor and the spectator
    Philosophia 7 (1): 197-203. 1977.
  •  24
    Human Morality’s Authority
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 55 (4). 1995.
    A central theme of Samuel Scheffler’s impressive Human Morality is that “a considered view of the relation between morality and the individual” requires distinguishing frequently confused issues concerning morality’s content, scope, authority, and deliberative role, and appreciating interrelations among these. He suggests a nice example of the latter. Some are inclined to believe morality lacks the overriding authority others claim it to have because they assume that morality’s content is string…Read more
  •  60
    Pleasure as Ultimate Good in Sidgwick’s Ethics
    The Monist 58 (3): 475-489. 1974.
    The notion of pleasure lies at the very heart of Sidgwick’s moral philosophy. For Sidgwick holds not merely that pleasure is a good, but that ultimately it is the only good. And hence it is the good of pleasure which grounds his utilitarianism.
  •  5
    Responsibility within Relations
    In Brian Feltham & John Cottingham (eds.), Partiality and Impartiality: Morality, Special Relationships, and the Wider World, Oxford University Press. 2010.
  •  31
    From Morality to Virtue and Back? (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 54 (3): 695-701. 1994.
  •  43
    On Schiffer’s Desires
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 17 (2): 193-198. 1979.
  •  34
    Review: Smith's Moral Problem (review)
    Philosophical Quarterly 46 (185). 1996.
  •  54
    Desires, Reasons, and Causes
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 67 (2): 436-443. 2003.
    Jonathan Dancy’s Practical Reality makes a significant contribution to clarifying the relationship between desire and reasons for acting, both the normative reasons we seek in deliberation and the motivating reasons we cite in explanation. About the former, Dancy argues that, not only are normative reasons not all grounded in desires, but, more radically, the fact that one desires something is never itself a normative reason. And he argues that desires fail to figure in motivating reasons also, …Read more
  •  424
    Virtue Ethics (edited book)
    Wiley-Blackwell. 2002.
    _ Virtue Ethics_ collects, for the first time, the main classical sources and the central contemporary expressions of virtue ethics approach to normative ethical theory. Edited and introduced by Stephen Darwall, these readings are essential for anyone interested in normative theory. Introduced by Stephen Darwall, this collection brings together classic and contemporary readings which define and advance the literature on virtue ethics. Includes six essays which respond to the classic sources. Inc…Read more
  •  45
    Morality and Principle
    In David Bakhurst, Margaret Olivia Little & Brad Hooker (eds.), Thinking about reasons: themes from the philosophy of Jonathan Dancy, Oxford University Press. pp. 168. 2013.
  •  49
    Respect, Concern, and Membership
    In Hans Bernhard Schmid, Christoph Henning & Dieter Thomä (eds.), Social Capital, Social Identities: From Ownership to Belonging, De Gruyter. pp. 93-104. 2014.
  •  655
    Consequentialism (edited book)
    Blackwell. 2003.
    Consequentialism collects, for the first time, both the main classical sources and the central contemporary expressions of this important position. Edited and introduced by Stephen Darwall, these readings are essential for anyone interested in normative ethics.
  •  28
    The Rejection of Consequentialism by Samuel Scheffler (review)
    Journal of Philosophy 81 (4): 220-226. 1984.
  •  179
    Abolishing morality
    Synthese 72 (1). 1987.
    Peer Reviewed.
  •  74
    The Development of Ethics
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 19 (1): 131-147. 2011.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  11
    How Should Ethics Relate to (the Rest of) Philosophy?: Moore's Legacy
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 41 (S1): 1-20. 2003.
  •  25
    Practical Skepticism and the Reasons for Action
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 8 (2). 1978.
    At least since Descartes's Meditations philosophers in the West have been concerned to defend the rationality of our beliefs from the threat of epistemological skepticism. The idea that there might be nothing which we know, or more radically, which we have even the slightest reason to believe, is one that many philosophers have thought to be deserving of serious attention. It seems somewhat odd, therefore, that there has not been similar attention given to what one might call practical skepticis…Read more