New Haven, Connecticut, United States of America
  •  17
    7. Choosing between the Theories
    In Death, Yale University Press. pp. 132-169. 2012.
  •  19
    1. Thinking about Death
    In Death, Yale University Press. pp. 1-5. 2012.
  •  16
    4. Descartes’ Argument
    In Death, Yale University Press. pp. 57-68. 2012.
  •  8
    16. Conclusion: An Invitation
    In Death, Yale University Press. pp. 362-364. 2012.
  •  37
    5. Plato on the Immortality of the Soul
    In Death, Yale University Press. pp. 69-97. 2012.
  •  101
    11. Immortality
    In Death, Yale University Press. pp. 234-246. 2012.
  •  10
    Acknowledgments
    In Death, Yale University Press. 2012.
  •  18
    9. Two Surprising Claims about Death
    In Death, Yale University Press. pp. 186-204. 2012.
  •  5
    Suggestions for Further Reading
    In Death, Yale University Press. pp. 369-370. 2012.
  •  23
    8. The Nature of Death
    In Death, Yale University Press. pp. 170-185. 2012.
  •  5
    13. Other Aspects of Death
    In Death, Yale University Press. pp. 264-281. 2012.
  •  7
    Index
    In Death, Yale University Press. pp. 371-376. 2012.
  •  25
    15. Suicide
    In Death, Yale University Press. pp. 318-361. 2012.
  •  82
    The paradox of methods
    Politics, Philosophy and Economics 17 (2): 148-168. 2018.
    Many proposed moral principles are such that it would be difficult or impossible to always correctly identify which act is required by that principle in a given situation. To deal with this problem, theorists typically offer various methods of determining what to do in the face of epistemic limitations, and we are then told that the right thing to do – given these limitations – is to perform the act identified by the given method. But since the method and the underlying principle can diverge, it…Read more
  •  9
    Vorlesungen zur marxistisch-leninistischen Asthetik
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 35 (3): 366-367. 1977.
  •  410
    Death
    Yale University Press. 2012.
    There is one thing we can be sure of: we are all going to die. But once we accept that fact, the questions begin. In this thought-provoking book, philosophy professor Shelly Kagan examines the myriad questions that arise when we confront the meaning of mortality. Do we have reason to believe in the existence of immortal souls? Or should we accept an account according to which people are just material objects, nothing more? Can we make sense of the idea of surviving the death of one’s body? If I …Read more
  •  635
  •  71
    The Costs of Transitivity: Thoughts on Larry Temkin’s Rethinking the Good
    Journal of Moral Philosophy 12 (4): 462-478. 2015.
    In Rethinking the Good, Larry Temkin argues that the common belief in the transitivity of better than is incompatible with various other value judgments to which many of us are deeply committed; accordingly, we should take seriously the possibility that the better than relation is not, in fact, a transitive one. However, although Temkin is right, I think, about the mutual incompatibility of the beliefs in question, for the most part his examples don’t leave me inclined to deny transitivity. None…Read more
  •  573
    Rethinking intrinsic value
    The Journal of Ethics 2 (4): 277-297. 1998.
    According to the dominant philosophical tradition, intrinsic value must depend solely upon intrinsic properties. By appealing to various examples, however, I argue that we should at least leave open the possibility that in some cases intrinsic value may be based in part on relational properties. Indeed, I argue that we should even be open to the possibility that an object''s intrinsic value may sometimes depend (in part) on its instrumental value. If this is right, of course, then the traditiona…Read more
  •  47
    Donagan on the Sins of Consequentialism
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 17 (3). 1987.
    Most intuitively forceful criticisms of utilitarianism, I believe, reduce to two basic objections. Both arise from the relentlessness of the utilitarian injunction to promote the overall good. On the one hand, this means that agents are permitted to perform an act of any kind whatsoever–provided only that the consequences of that act are better than those of any alternative. In particular, this means that it is permissible to impose tremendous sacrifices or injuries upon someone, if this is the …Read more
  •  22
    An Introduction to Ill-Being
    Oxford Studies in Normative Ethics 4 261-88. 2014.
    Typically, discussions of well-being focus almost exclusively on the positive aspects of well-being, those elements which directly contribute to a life going well, or better. It is generally assumed, without comment, that there is no need to explicitly discuss ill-being as well—that is, the part of the theory of well-being that specifies the elements which directly contribute to a life going badly, or less well—since (or so it is thought) this raises no special difficulties or problems. But this…Read more
  •  466
    The Limits of Well-Being
    Social Philosophy and Policy 9 (2): 169-189. 1992.
    What are the limits of well-being? This question nicely captures one of the central debates concerning the nature of the individual human good. For rival theories differ as to what sort of facts directly constitute a person's being well-off. On some views, well-being is limited to the presence of pleasure and the absence of pain. But other views push the boundaries of well-being beyond this, so that it encompasses a variety of mental states, not merely pleasure alone. Some theories then draw the…Read more
  •  396
    Thinking about Cases
    Social Philosophy and Policy 18 (2): 44. 2001.
    Anyone who reflects on the way we go about arguing for or against moral claims is likely to be struck by the central importance we give to thinking about cases. Intuitive reactions to cases—real or imagined—are carefully noted, and then appealed to as providing reason to accept various claims. When trying on a general moral theory for size, for example, we typically get a feel for its overall plausibility by considering its implications in a range of cases. Similarly, when we try to refine the s…Read more
  •  421
    Me and My Life
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 94 309-324. 1994.
    In this paper I take some initial steps toward exploring and motivating the suggestion that quality of life and level of well-being do not come to the same thing.
  •  137
    Why Study Philosophy?
    Frontiers of Philosophy in China 8 (2): 258-265. 2013.
  •  3
  •  72
    Rethinking intrinsic value
    The Journal of Ethics 2 (4): 97--114. 2005.
    According to the dominant philosophical tradition, intrinsic value must depend solely upon intrinsic properties. By appealing to various examples, however, I argue that we should at least leave open the possibility that in some cases intrinsic value may be based in part on relational properties. Indeed, I argue that we should even be open to the possibility that an object's intrinsic value may sometimes depend on its instrumental value. If this is right, of course, then the traditional contrast …Read more
  •  19
    Donagan On The Sins Of Consequentialism
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 17 (3): 643-653. 1987.
    Most intuitively forceful criticisms of utilitarianism, I believe, reduce to two basic objections. Both arise from the relentlessness of the utilitarian injunction to promote the overall good. On the one hand, this means that agents are permitted to perform an act of any kind whatsoever–provided only that the consequences of that act are better than those of any alternative. In particular, this means that it is permissible to impose tremendous sacrifices or injuries upon someone, if this is the …Read more