New Haven, Connecticut, United States of America
  •  4
    13. Other Aspects of Death
    In Death, Yale University Press. pp. 264-281. 2012.
  •  23
    8. The Nature of Death
    In Death, Yale University Press. pp. 170-185. 2012.
  •  5
    Index
    In Death, Yale University Press. pp. 371-376. 2012.
  •  24
    15. Suicide
    In Death, Yale University Press. pp. 318-361. 2012.
  •  81
    The paradox of methods
    Politics, Philosophy and Economics 17 (2): 148-168. 2018.
    Many proposed moral principles are such that it would be difficult or impossible to always correctly identify which act is required by that principle in a given situation. To deal with this problem, theorists typically offer various methods of determining what to do in the face of epistemic limitations, and we are then told that the right thing to do – given these limitations – is to perform the act identified by the given method. But since the method and the underlying principle can diverge, it…Read more
  •  9
    Vorlesungen zur marxistisch-leninistischen Asthetik
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 35 (3): 366-367. 1977.
  •  408
    Me and My Life
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 94 309-324. 1994.
    In this paper I take some initial steps toward exploring and motivating the suggestion that quality of life and level of well-being do not come to the same thing.
  •  137
    Why Study Philosophy?
    Frontiers of Philosophy in China 8 (2): 258-265. 2013.
  •  3
  •  68
    Rethinking intrinsic value
    The Journal of Ethics 2 (4): 97--114. 2005.
    According to the dominant philosophical tradition, intrinsic value must depend solely upon intrinsic properties. By appealing to various examples, however, I argue that we should at least leave open the possibility that in some cases intrinsic value may be based in part on relational properties. Indeed, I argue that we should even be open to the possibility that an object's intrinsic value may sometimes depend on its instrumental value. If this is right, of course, then the traditional contrast …Read more
  •  19
    Donagan On The Sins Of Consequentialism
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 17 (3): 643-653. 1987.
    Most intuitively forceful criticisms of utilitarianism, I believe, reduce to two basic objections. Both arise from the relentlessness of the utilitarian injunction to promote the overall good. On the one hand, this means that agents are permitted to perform an act of any kind whatsoever–provided only that the consequences of that act are better than those of any alternative. In particular, this means that it is permissible to impose tremendous sacrifices or injuries upon someone, if this is the …Read more
  •  83
    Causation and Responsibility
    American Philosophical Quarterly 25 (4). 1988.
  •  480
    Infinite value and finitely additive value theory
    Journal of Philosophy 94 (1): 5-26. 1997.
    000000001. Introduction Call a theory of the good—be it moral or prudential—aggregative just in case (1) it recognizes local (or location-relative) goodness, and (2) the goodness of states of affairs is based on some aggregation of local goodness. The locations for local goodness might be points or regions in time, space, or space-time; or they might be people, or states of nature.1 Any method of aggregation is allowed: totaling, averaging, measuring the equality of the distribution, measuring t…Read more
  •  67
    Normative Ethics
    Westview Press. 1998.
    Cover -- Half Title -- Title -- Copyright -- Dedication -- Contents -- Acknowledgments -- 1 Preliminaries -- 1.1 What Normative Ethics Is -- 1.2 What Normative Ethics Is Not -- 1.3 Defending Normative Theories -- 1.4 Factors and Foundations -- PART I FACTORS -- 2 The Good -- 2.1 Promoting the Good -- 2.2 Well-Being -- 2.3 The Total View -- 2.4 Equality -- 2.5 Culpability, Fairness, and Desert -- 2.6 Consequentialism -- 3 Doing Harm -- 3.1 Deontology -- 3.2 Thresholds -- 3.3 The Scope of the Cons…Read more
  •  1228
    Do I Make a Difference?
    Philosophy and Public Affairs 39 (2): 105-141. 2011.
  •  831
    What’s Wrong with Speciesism
    Journal of Applied Philosophy 33 (1): 1-21. 2015.
    Peter Singer famously argued in Animal Liberation that almost all of us are speciesists, unjustifiably favoring the interests of humans over the similar interests of other animals. Although I long found that charge compelling, I now find myself having doubts. This article starts by trying to get clear about the nature of speciesism, and then argues that Singer's attempt to show that speciesism is a mere prejudice is unsuccessful. I also argue that most of us are not actually speciesists at all, …Read more
  •  109
    The Geometry of Desert
    Oxford University Press. 2005.
    Moral desert -- Fault forfeits first -- Desert graphs -- Skylines -- Other shapes -- Placing peaks -- The ratio view -- Similar offense -- Graphing comparative desert -- Variation -- Groups -- Desert taken as a whole -- Reservations.
  •  63
    Review: Replies to My Critics (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 51 (4). 1991.
  •  12
    30. Equality and Desert
    In Louis P. Pojman & Owen McLeod (eds.), What Do We Deserve?: A Reader on Justice and Desert, Oxford University Press. pp. 298. 1999.
  •  90
    Causation, liability, and internalism
    Philosophy and Public Affairs 15 (1): 41-59. 1986.
  •  306
    The structure of normative ethics
    Philosophical Perspectives 6 223-242. 1992.
  •  4
    The Argument from Liberty
    In Joel Feinberg, Jules L. Coleman & Allen E. Buchanan (eds.), In Harm's Way: Essays in Honor of Joel Feinberg, Cambridge University Press. pp. 16--41. 1994.
  •  6
    Normative Ethics
    Mind 109 (434): 373-377. 1998.
  •  202
    Defending options
    Ethics 104 (2): 333-351. 1994.
  •  45
    XIV*—Me and My Life
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 94 (1): 309-324. 1994.
    Shelly Kagan; XIV*—Me and My Life, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 94, Issue 1, 1 June 1994, Pages 309–324, https://doi.org/10.1093/aristotelian.
  •  1342
    The limits of morality
    Oxford University Press. 1989.
    Most people believe that there are limits to the sacrifices that morality can demand. Although it would often be meritorious, we are not, in fact, morally required to do all that we can to promote overall good. What's more, most people also believe that certain types of acts are simply forbidden, morally off limits, even when necessary for promoting the overall good. In this provocative analysis Kagan maintains that despite the intuitive appeal of these views, they cannot be adequately defended.…Read more
  •  85
    Replies to My Critics (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 51 (4): 919-928. 1991.