• Alex C. Michalos, Militarism and the Quality of Life (review)
    Philosophy in Review 11 91-94. 1991.
  •  8
    Can God’s existence be proven by logic? Are computers smart enough to follow rules—or to cheat? What is an out-of-body experience? How can tables be solid when physicists say they’re made of subatomic particles that are only probability functions? Does science depend on trust? What is conscience? Does it come from God? From religious teaching? Social training? Is it rational to pursue your own self-interest? Can we all survive if we do this? In this collection of stories and dialogues Trudy Govi…Read more
  •  32
    Presuppositions, Conditions, and Consequences
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 1 (4). 1972.
    An analysis of necessary condition and presupposition reveals that, as logical relations, these notions are basically similar to each other and different from the notion of entailment or other ‘if-then’ relations of logical consequence. Both necessary condition and presupposition seem to be two-directional in a rather peculiar way. Appreciating this is helpful in interpreting philosophers such as Kant and Strawson who have relied extensively on these relations in constructing the philosophical a…Read more
  •  8
    Getting Rid of the Big Bad Wolf
    Philosophy 56 (216). 1981.
  •  31
    Dilemmas of Trust
    Carleton University Press. 1998.
    Trust facilitates communication, love, friendship, and co-operation and is fundamentally important to human relationships and personal development. Using examples from daily life, interviews, literature, and film, Govier describes the role of trust in friendship and in family relationships as well as the connection between self-trust, self-respect, and self-esteem. She examines the reasons we trust or distrust others and ourselves, and the expectations and vulnerabilities that accompany those at…Read more
  •  75
    In the context of redressing wrongs of the past, the importance of acknowledgement is often urged. It figures significantly, for instance, in the final report of South Africa's Truth and Reconciliation Commission and in the 1996 Canadian Royal Commiss ion Report on Aboriginal Peoples. In both documents a central theme is that acknowledging wrongs of the past is a key first step towards healing and reconciliation. Several recent statements about public apology also urge that moral apologies are s…Read more
  •  36
    How can we respond in the aftermath of wrongdoing? How can social trust be restored in the wake of intense political conflict? In this challenging work, philosopher Trudy Govier explores central dilemmas of political reconciliation, employing illustrative material from Rwanda, Sierra Leone, South Africa, Australia, Canada, Peru, and elsewhere. Govier stresses that reconciliation is fundamentally about relationships. Whether through means of truth commissions, apologies, community processes, or c…Read more
  •  47
    Belief, Values, and the Will
    Dialogue 15 (4): 642-663. 1976.
    In this paper I shall presuppose that: logic and epistemology are disciplines which supply us with normative statements pertaining to states of belief. as such, logic and epistemology have implications concerning what we ought and ought not to believe. as such, logic and epistemology presuppose that there is some sense in which a person controls what he believes — some sense in which ‘can’ has a place in contexts where one comes to believe things.
  •  53
    Trust and the problem of national reconciliation
    with Wilhelm Verwoerd
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 32 (2): 178-205. 2002.
    The authors propose a conception of national reconciliation based on the building or rebuilding of trust between parties alienated by conflict. It is by no means obvious what reconciliation between large groups of people amounts to in practice or how it should be understood in theory. Lack of conceptual clarity can be illustrated with particular reference to postapartheid South Africa, where reconciliation between whites and blacks was a major goal of the Mandela government and the Truth and Rec…Read more
  •  5
    Applying Ethics (review)
    Teaching Philosophy 6 (1): 54-56. 1983.
  •  48
    Is Conscientiousness Always—or Ever—a Virtue?
    Dialogue 11 (2): 241-251. 1972.
    On most views of the nature of moral judgments, it is possible for a person to be mistaken in the belief that it is right to act in a certain way. When someone believes that it is right to do something, does that thing on the basis of such a belief, and yet in so doing commits deeds which are wrong by moral standards other than his own, we do not quite know whether to praise him for his conscientiousness while condemning his actions. He acts according to his conscience and does what he believes …Read more
  •  45
    Analogies and Missing Premises
    Informal Logic 11 (3). 1989.
  •  7
    Book reviews (review)
    with Charles Arthur Willard, Erik C. W. Krabbe, Lita Lundquist, Douglas Walton, and Peter Jan Schellens
    Argumentation 6 (4): 473-493. 1993.
  •  110
    Forgiveness and the Unforgivable
    American Philosophical Quarterly 36 (1). 1999.
  •  18
    Nuclear Illusion and Individual Obligations
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 13 (4). 1983.
    Until very recently the topic of nuclear armaments and the prospects of global nuclear war have been relatively inconspicuous in the work of philosophers. With some exceptions, these and related themes have not figured prominently in the academic writings of philosophers; nor have they occupied space commensurate with their importance in courses and anthologies on applied ethics. Helen Caldicott's widely circulated film, ‘If You Love This Planet,’ and Jonathan Schell's moving book, The Fate of t…Read more
  •  93
    What's Wrong with Slippery Slope Arguments?
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 12 (2). 1982.
    Slippery slope arguments are commonly thought to be fallacious. But is there a single fallacy which they all commit? A study of applied logic texts reveals competing diagnoses of the supposed error, and several recent authors take slippery slope arguments seriously. Clearly, there is room for comment. I shall give evidence of divergence on the question of what sort of argument constitutes a slippery slope, distinguish four different types of argument which have all been deemed to be slippery slo…Read more
  •  30
    Critical thinking as argument analysis
    Argumentation 3 (2): 115-126. 1989.
  • My interlocutor
    In F. H. van Eemeren, Peter Houtlosser, Haft-van Rees & A. M. (eds.), Considering pragma-dialectics: a festschrift for Frans H. van Eemeren on the occasion of his 60th birthday, L. Erlbaum Associates. pp. 87. 2006.
  •  2
    The Metaphysics of G. E. Moore
    Philosophical Books 25 (1): 27-29. 1984.
  •  16
    Ad Hominen
    Teaching Philosophy 6 (1): 13-24. 1983.
  •  3
  •  13
    How do Humans Think? How should we think? Almost all of philosophy and a great deal else depends in large part on the answers that we provide to such questions. Yet they are almost impossible to deal with in isolation; notions about nature of thought are almost bound to connect with metaphysical notions about where ideas come from, with notions about appropriate arenas for certainty, doubt, and belief, and hence with moral and religious ideas. The Western tradition of thinking about thinking tak…Read more
  •  32
    A conception of invitational forgiveness
    with Colin Hirano
    Journal of Social Philosophy 39 (3): 429-444. 2008.
    No Abstract