•  101
    Supervenience and anomalous monism: Blackburn on Davidson
    Philosophical Studies 71 (1): 59-79. 1993.
    In his paper "Supervenience Revisisted", Simon Blackburn redeployed his novel modal argument against moral realism as an argument against Donald Davidson's position of 'anomalous monism' in the philosophy of mind (Blackburn 1985).' I shall assess this redeployment. In the first part of this paper, I shall lay out Blackburn's argument. In the second and longer part I shall examine Davidson's denial of psychophysical laws in the light of this argument
  •  100
    The Creative Theory of Art
    American Philosophical Quarterly 32 (4). 1995.
  •  99
    Epistemic/Non‐epistemic Dependence
    Noûs 836-857. 2018.
    I foreground the principle of epistemic dependence. I isolate that relation and distinguish it from other relations and note what it does and does not entail. In particular, I distinguish between dependence and necessitation. This has many interesting consequences. On the negative side, many standard arguments in epistemology are subverted. More positively, once we are liberated from the necessary and sufficient conditions project, many fruitful paths for future epistemological investigation ope…Read more
  •  98
    Aesthetic Realism 1
    In Jerrold Levinson (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Aesthetics, Oxford University Press. 2005.
  •  97
    Moral modus ponens
    Ratio 5 (2): 177-193. 1992.
  •  96
    Reply to Larry Shiner on architecture
    Sztuka I Filozofia (Art and Philosophy) 35 254. 2009.
  •  96
    Supervenience, reduction, and infinite disjunction
    Philosophia 26 (1-2): 321-330. 1998.
    Can a certain sort of property supervene on another sort of property without reducing to it? Many philosophers find the superveniencel irreducibility combination attractive in the philosophy of mind and in moral philosophy (Davidson 1980 and Moore 1903). They think that mental properties supervene upon physical properties but do not reduce to them, or that moral properties supervene upon natural properties without reducing to them. Other philosophers have tried to show that the combination is ul…Read more
  •  95
    Music seems mysterious, and our experience of some can have a peculiar depth. I think we should embrace this mysteriousness and not try to explain it away. There is something about music and our experience of it that is indescribable, and sometimes wonderfully indescribable. I here explore a view of music that is unashamedly mystical. However, this mysticism takes a particular form. Near the entry on “music” in Robert Audi’s Dictionary of Philosophy (Audi 1999) is an entry on “mysticism” by Will…Read more
  •  95
    Beauty
    In Jerrold Levinson (ed.), Oxford Companion to Aesthetics, Oxford University Press. 2003.
    I shall discuss several related issues about beauty. These are: (1) The place of beauty among other aesthetic properties. (2) The general principle of aesthetic supervenience. (3) The problem of aesthetic relevance. (4) The distinction between free and dependent beauty. (5) The primacy of our appreciation of free beauty over our appreciation of dependent beauty. (6) Personal beauty as a species of beauty. (7) The metaphysics of beauty.
  •  94
    Explaining supervenience: Moral and mental
    Journal of Philosophical Research 22 (April): 509-518. 1997.
    I defend the view that supervenience relations need not be explained. My view is that some supervenience relations are brute, and explanatorily ultimate. I examine an argument of Terrence Horgan and Mark Timmons. They aim to rehabilitate John Mackie’s metaphysical queerness argument. But the explanations of supervenience that Horgan and Timmons demand are semantic explanations. I criticize their attempt to explain psychophysical supervenience in this fashion. I then turn to their ‘Twin Earth’ ar…Read more
  •  91
    Music, Essential Metaphor, and Private Language
    American Philosophical Quarterly 48 (1): 1. 2011.
    Music is elusive. describing it is problematic. In particular its aesthetic properties cannot be captured in literal description. Beyond very simple terms, they cannot be literally described. In this sense, the aesthetic description of music is essentially nonliteral. An adequate aesthetic description of music must have resort to metaphor or other nonliteral devices. I maintain that this is because of the nature of the aesthetic properties being described. I defend this view against an apparentl…Read more
  •  91
    Hume, taste, and teleology
    Philosophical Papers 23 (1): 1-18. 1994.
  •  81
    The unimportance of the avant garde
    Revista di Estetica 1. 2007.
  •  81
    II—Moral Dependence and Natural Properties
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 91 (1): 221-243. 2017.
    I explore the Because Constraint—the idea that moral facts depend on natural facts and that moral judgements ought to respect the dependence of moral facts on natural facts. I consider several issues concerning its clarification and importance.
  •  75
    Piękno
    Sztuka I Filozofia (Art and Philosophy) 30 254. 2007.
  •  66
    Aesthetic/sensory dependence
    British Journal of Aesthetics 38 (1): 66-81. 1998.
  •  66
    Explaining human cruelty
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 29 (3): 245-246. 2006.
    I ask four questions: (1) Why should we think that our hominid ancestor's predation is not just a causal influence but the main causal factor responsible for human cruelty? (2) Why not think of human cruelty as a necessary part of a syndrome in which other phenomena are necessarily involved? (3) What definitions of cruelty does Nell propose that we operate with? And (4) what about the meaning of cruelty for human beings?
  •  63
    Rationality and moral realism
    Ratio 25 (3): 345-364. 2012.
    What can a moral realist say about why we should take morality seriously and about the relation between morality and rationality? I take off from Christine Korsgaard's criticism of moral realism on this score. The aim is to achieve an understanding of the relation between moral and rational properties and of the role of practical deliberation on a realist view. I argue that the justification for being concerned with rational and moral normative properties may not be an aspect of our minds to whi…Read more
  •  62
    Against the sociology of art
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 32 (2): 206-218. 2002.
    Aesthetic theories of art refuse to go away. In spite of decades of criticism and derision, a minority of thinkers stubbornly persist in maintaining that we need a general theory of art that makes essential appeal to beauty, elegance, daintiness, and other aesthetic properties.1 However, those who approach the theory of art from a sociological point of view tend to be skeptical about any account of art that appeals to aesthetic properties in a fundamental way. This skepticism takes two overlappi…Read more
  •  58
    Scepticism about Scepticism
    Philosophy 91 (1): 109-118. 2016.
  •  57
    Groundrules in the Philosophy of Art
    Philosophy 70 (274). 1995.
    What are the groundrules in the philosophy of art? What criteria of adequacy should we use for assessing theories of art?
  •  56
    I argue that there is a problem for a wide class of theories of art that arises from counterexamples drawn from everyday artistic activity, rather than high artworld artistic activity. I explore how the counterexample functions. Part of the point is to reflect on methodological issues concerning the use of examples when considering theories of art. We will also see why thinking about everyday cases is theoretically significant.
  •  52
    The Metaphysics of Beauty
    Cornell University Press. 2001.
    In chapters ranging from "The Beautiful, the Dainty, and the Dumpy" to "Skin-deep or In the Eye of the Beholder?" Nick Zangwill investigates the nature of beauty as we conceive it, and as it is in itself. The notion of beauty is currently attracting increased interest, particularly in philosophical aesthetics and in discussions of our experiences and judgments about art. In The Metaphysics of Beauty, Zangwill argues that it is essential to beauty that it depends on the ordinary features of thing…Read more
  •  38
    Epistemic Pluralism
    Metaphilosophy 51 (4): 485-498. 2020.
    In this paper epistemic pluralism concerning knowledge is taken to be the claim that very different facts may constitute knowledge. The paper argues for pluralism by arguing that very different facts can constitute the knowledge‐making links between beliefs and facts. If pluralism is right, we need not anxiously seek a unified account of the links between beliefs and facts that partly constitute knowledge in different cases of knowledge. The paper argues that no good reasons have been put forwar…Read more
  •  35
    I probe the judgments of the agreeable that we make about food and drink. I first separate different concerns that we might have with food and drink. After that, I address expressive language by first sketching an evolutionary language-game-theoretic approach for referential language. I then try to extend it to expressive language, showing how expressive signaling might be likely to evolve. Given an account of expressive prediction, and its point, I turn to the Frege-Geach problem for the agreeabl…Read more
  •  35
    Aesthetic Creation
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 66 (4): 416-418. 2008.