•  128
    Chaos out of order: Quantum mechanics, the correspondence principle and chaos
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 28 (2): 147-182. 1997.
    A vast amount of ink has been spilled in both the physics and the philosophy literature on the measurement problem in quantum mechanics. Important as it is, this problem is but one aspect of the more general issue of how, if at all, classical properties can emerge from the quantum descriptions of physical systems. In this paper we will study another aspect of the more general issue-the emergence of classical chaos-which has been receiving increasing attention from physicists but which has largel…Read more
  •  69
    Recent work on time travel
    In Jeremy Butterfield & John Earman (eds.), , . 1977.
  •  69
    Covariance, invariance, and the equivalence of frames
    Foundations of Physics 4 (2): 267-289. 1974.
    This paper represents an attempt to clarify a number of long-standing issues concerning the nature and status of the special and general principles of relativity in particular and symmetry or invariance principles in general. An analysis of the active and passive interpretations of symmetry operations is offered. This analysis yields an evaluation of the old covariance-invariance issue. It also demonstrates that the passive interpretation, insofar as it is not trivial, is parasitic on the active…Read more
  •  194
    The universality of laws
    Philosophy of Science 45 (2): 173-181. 1978.
    Various senses in which laws of nature are supposed to be "universal" are distinguished. Conditions designed to capture the content of the more important of these senses are proposed and the relations among these conditions are examined. The status of universality requirements is briefly discussed
  •  85
    Foundations of Space-Time Theories: Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science (edited book)
    with Clark N. Glymour and John J. Stachel
    University of Minnesota Press. 1974.
    Some Philosophical Prehistory of General Relativity As history, my remarks will form rather a medley. If they can claim any sort of unity (apart from a ...
  •  86
    Relativistic Causality in Algebraic Quantum Field Theory
    International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 28 (1): 1-48. 2014.
    This paper surveys the issue of relativistic causality within the framework of algebraic quantum field theory . In doing so, we distinguish various notions of causality formulated in the literature and study their relationships, and thereby we offer what we hope to be a useful taxonomy. We propose that the most direct expression of relativistic causality in AQFT is captured not by the spectrum condition but rather by the axiom of local primitive causality, in that it entails a form of local dete…Read more
  •  71
    There is currently no viable alternative to the Bayesian analysis of scientific inference, yet the available versions of Bayesianism fail to do justice to several aspects of the testing and confirmation of scientific hypotheses. Bayes or Bust? provides the first balanced treatment of the complex set of issues involved in this nagging conundrum in the philosophy of science. Both Bayesians and anti-Bayesians will find a wealth of new insights on topics ranging from Bayes's original paper to contem…Read more
  •  12
    The Nature and Recognition of Scientific Progress
    In Jeremy Butterfield & John Earman (eds.), , . 1977.
  •  51
    In his 1768 essay ‘Concerning the Ultimate Foundation of the Differentiation of the Regions in Space’, Kant used incongruent counterparts in an attempt to refute a Leibnizian-relationist account of space. It is hard to imagine that scholars could be more divided on how to understand Kant’s argument and on how to assess its effectiveness. Two years later in 1770 incongruent counterparts resurface in Kant’s Inaugural Dissertation, this time as part of a proof that our knowledge of space is intuiti…Read more
  •  85
    Tolerance for spacetime singularities
    Foundations of Physics 26 (5): 623-640. 1996.
    A common reaction to the Penrose-Hawking singularity theorems is that Einstein's general theory of relativity contains the seeds of its own destruction. This attitude is critically examined. A more tolerant attitude toward spacetime singularities is recommended
  •  31
    Einstein and Singularities
    with Jean Eisenstaedt
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 30 (2): 185-235. 1998.
    Except for a few brief periods, Einstein was uninterested in analysing the nature of the spacetime singularities that appeared in solutions to his gravitational field equations for general relativity. The existence of such monstrosities reinforced his conviction that general relativity was an incomplete theory which would be superseded by a singularity-free unified field theory. Nevertheless, on a number of occasions between 1916 and the end of his life, Einstein was forced to confront singulari…Read more
  •  153
    Who's afraid of absolute space?
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 48 (3): 287-319. 1970.
    No abstract
  •  23
    Lambda: The Constant That Refuses to Die
    Archive for History of Exact Sciences 55 (3): 189-220. 2001.
  •  183
    Philosophy of Physics (edited book)
    Elsevier. 2006.
    The ambition of this volume is twofold: to provide a comprehensive overview of the field and to serve as an indispensable reference work for anyone who wants to work in it. For example, any philosopher who hopes to make a contribution to the topic of the classical-quantum correspondence will have to begin by consulting Klaas Landsman’s chapter. The organization of this volume, as well as the choice of topics, is based on the conviction that the important problems in the philosophy of physics ari…Read more
  •  29
    The Cosmos of Science: Essays of Exploration (edited book)
    with John D. Norton
    University of Pittsburgh Press. 1997.
    The inaugural volume of the series, devoted to the work of philosopher Adolf Grünbaum, encompasses the philosophical problems of space, time, and cosmology, the ...
  •  329
    In Part I, we presented and motivated a new formulation of Humean Supervenience about Laws of Nature (HS). Here in Part II, we present an epistemological argument in defense of HS, thus formulated. Our contention is that one can combine a modest realism about laws of nature with a proper recognition of the importance of empirical testability in the epistemology of science only if one accepts HS
  •  617
    What price spacetime substantivalism? The hole story
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 38 (4): 515-525. 1987.
    Spacetime substantivalism leads to a radical form of indeterminism within a very broad class of spacetime theories which include our best spacetime theory, general relativity. Extending an argument from Einstein, we show that spacetime substantivalists are committed to very many more distinct physical states than these theories' equations can determine, even with the most extensive boundary conditions
  •  91
    The Hawking Information Loss Paradox: The Anatomy of a Controversy
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 50 (2): 189-229. 1999.
    Stephen Hawking has argued that universes containing evaporating black holes can evolve from pure initial states to mixed final ones. Such evolution is non-unitary and so contravenes fundamental quantum principles on which Hawking's analysis was based. It disables the retrodiction of the universe's initial state from its final one, and portends the time-asymmetry of quantum gravity. Small wonder that Hawking's paradox has met with considerable resistance. Here we use a simple result for C*-algeb…Read more
  •  191
    Schrödinger averred that entanglement is the characteristic trait of quantum mechanics. The first part of this paper is simultaneously an exploration of Schrödinger’s claim and an investigation into the distinction between mere entanglement and genuine quantum entanglement. The typical discussion of these matters in the philosophical literature neglects the structure of the algebra of observables, implicitly assuming a tensor product structure of the simple Type I factor algebras used in ordinar…Read more
  •  3
    Cosmos of Science: Philosophical Problems of the Internal and External Worlds (edited book)
    University of Pittsburgh Press. 1998.
    The inaugural volume of the series, devoted to the work of philosopher Adolf Grünbaum, encompasses the philosophical problems of space, time, and cosmology, the nature of scientific methodology, and the foundations of psychoanalysis
  •  120
    Fulling non‐uniqueness and the Unruh effect
    with Aristidis Arageorgis and and Laura Ruetsche
    Philosophy of Science 70 (1): 164-202. 2003.
    We discuss the intertwined topics of Fulling non-uniqueness and the Unruh effect. The Fulling quantization, which is in some sense the natural one for an observer uniformly accelerated through Minkowski spacetime to adopt, is often heralded as a quantization of the Klein-Gordon field which is both physically relevant and unitarily inequivalent to the standard Minkowski quantization. We argue that the Fulling and Minkowski quantizations do not constitute a satisfactory example of physically relev…Read more
  •  37
    Remarks on Relational Theories of Motion
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 19 (1). 1989.
    In a recent article in this journal, Barbara Lariviere offers a very useful distinction between two ways of understanding the claims that Leibniz, or relational theorists in general, might wish to make about the nature of motion and the structure of space and time; viz., There is no real inertial structure to space-time.and There is a real inertial structure to space-time, but it is dynamical rather than absolute.Citing the authority of Weyl, the author argues that L1 is untenable; indeed, the a…Read more
  •  425
    Causation: A matter of life and death
    Journal of Philosophy 73 (1): 5-25. 1976.
  •  174
    Exorcist XIV: The Wrath of Maxwell’s Demon. Part I. From Maxwell to Szilard
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 29 (4): 435-471. 1998.
    In this first part of a two-part paper, we describe efforts in the early decades of this century to restrict the extent of violations of the Second Law of thermodynamics that were brought to light by the rise of the kinetic theory and the identification of fluctuation phenomena. We show how these efforts mutated into Szilard’s proposal that Maxwell’s Demon is exorcised by proper attention to the entropy costs associated with the Demon’s memory and information acquisition. In the second part we w…Read more
  •  53
    Philosophical Problems of the Internal and External World (edited book)
    University of Pittsburgh Press. 1993.
    Now, considering the determinism or indeterminism of the world, ... The question of free will, and the mind-body problem, are two that come to mind. ...
  •  81
    Indeed, this is the first serious book-length study of the subject by a philosopher of science.