•  42
    Varieties of Religion Today (review)
    American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 81 (1): 156-160. 2007.
  •  55
    Purpose, Power, and Agency
    The Monist 75 (4): 423-444. 1992.
    There are various reasons for taking a second look at anything at all. One reason is to discern aspects which have been overlooked; another frequently related reason is to reappraise the value or relevance of whatever is being reconsidered. A thing might be deemed worthless or negligible because some feature or set of features has been overlooked. And this way of conceiving the thing might become so familiar, so entrenched, that it powerfully, because subtly, works against alternative conception…Read more
  •  30
    “The world is,” William James notes, “full of partial stories that run parallel to one another, beginning and ending at odd times. They mutually interlace and interfere at points, but we cannot unify them completely in our minds”. As a radical empiricist, he takes there to be more to experience than any of our stories or other forms of account can ever capture. Here as everywhere else, “ever not quite” and “ever not yet” qualify even our master strokes. As a radical pluralist, accordingly, he ta…Read more
  •  27
    Telling Tales Out of School: Pragmatic Reflections on Philosophical Storytelling
    Journal of Speculative Philosophy 27 (1): 1-32. 2013.
    ABSTRACT This article offers a critique of a deeply engrained tendency to narrate the story of American pragmatism exclusively or primarily in terms of modern European philosophy. While it suggests alternative stories, it is principally a metanarrative, an intentionally polemical story about our entrenched habits of philosophical storytelling. Indeed, the pragmatics of storytelling merits, especially in reference to historical accounts of American pragmatism, critical attention. The seemingly si…Read more
  •  64
    Present at the end?: Who will be there when the last stone is thrown?
    Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 46 (1): 9-20. 2010.
    From time to time, Peter H. Hare emphatically reminded me he was drawn to William James as a philosopher, not just a stylist. While Peter1 was throughout his life appreciative of James's efforts to articulate an ethics of belief (see, e.g., Hare 2003), he was skeptical of them in the context of religion. He felt compelled to hound the gods and their defenders (Hare and Madden 1969). Even so, the ethics of belief outlined and partly filled in by James provided Peter with crucial insights for deve…Read more
  •  66
    Striving to Speak in a Human Voice
    Review of Metaphysics 58 (2): 367-398. 2004.
    A. N. WHITEHEAD SUGGESTS philosophy is akin to poetry. Let me count the ways or, more exactly, identify four facets of this kinship. After touching upon these facets, I will in the second part of this paper focus directly on the relationship between being and articulation, regardless of the form in which being comes to expression. Then, in the third section, I offer Charles S. Peirce’s categoreal scheme as a compelling articulation of what are, arguably, the most ubiquitous and indeed basic feat…Read more
  • Charles Sanders Peirce., 1903 Harvard Lectures on
    In Jorge J. E. Gracia, Gregory M. Reichberg & Bernard N. Schumacher (eds.), The Classics of Western Philosophy: A Reader's Guide, Wiley-blackwell. pp. 453. 2003.
  •  11
    Truth, Rationality, and Pragmatism (review)
    International Philosophical Quarterly 42 (1): 122-124. 2002.
  •  8
    Semiotics from Peirce to Barthes (review)
    Newsletter of the Society for the Advancement of American Philosophy 17 (54): 8-10. 1989.
  •  13
    The Nature of Rationality
    International Philosophical Quarterly 35 (4): 491-494. 1995.
  •  26
    Love and Death—and Other Somatic Transactions
    Hypatia 17 (4): 163-172. 2002.
    This paper both elaborates and interrogates the transactional model of human experience at the center of Shannon W. Sullivan's Living Across and Through Skins. In particular, it highlights the need to supplement her account with a psychoanalytic reading of our gendered subjectivities. Moreover, it stresses the necessity to focus on such humanly important—and irreducibly somatic—phenomena as grief and eros.
  •  73
    One criticism of pragmatism, forcefully articulated by Stanley Cavell, is that pragmatism fails to deal with mourning, understood in the psychoanalytic sense as grief-work (Trauerarbeit). Such work would seemingly be as pertinent to philosophical investigations (especially ones conducted by pragmatists) as to psychoanalytic explorations. Finding such themes as mourning and loss in R. W. Emerson's writings, Cavell warns against assimilating Emerson's voice to that of American pragmatism, especial…Read more
  •  13
    The Grace and the Severity of the Ideal: John Dewey and the Transcendent (review)
    American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 80 (4): 625-628. 2006.
  • Index to Volume 12
    Journal of Speculative Philosophy 12 (4). 1998.
  •  17
    Woolf on Words
    Semiotics 108-116. 2000.
  •  6
    A Revised Portrait of Human Agency
    European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy 1 (1): 2-24. 2009.
    Anthony Giddens, Hans Joas, Margaret Archer, Norbert Wiley, and Eugene Halton (to name but a handful of such figures) are social theorists whose philosophical importance is all too often missed (or ignored) by professional philosophers. The main reason for this is obvious: they are by training and appointment social scientists, while professional philosophy tends to be an insular discipline. Disciplinary purity, like most other forms of this misplaced ideal, tends to insure insularity and vit...
  •  11
    Human Agency: The Habits of Our Being
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 26 (2): 153-168. 1988.
  •  232
    The Vanishing Subject of Contemporary Discourse: A Pragmatic Response
    Journal of Philosophy 87 (11): 644-655. 1990.
  •  109
    American Evasions of Foucault
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 36 (3): 329-351. 1998.
  •  16
    Time and Reality in American Philosophy (review)
    Process Studies 16 (4): 306-309. 1987.
  • : The essay explores how C. S. Peirce, especially in his mature thought, addressed the question of meaning. It underscores how he not only took meaning to be at bottom a function of our habits but also how he conceived these habits themselves to be functions of the histories in which they originate and operate. Hence, what I propose here is this: One of the most fruitful ways to interpret Peirce's own contribution to this question is to see his efforts as carrying forward the impetus intensified…Read more