K. Brad Wray

Aarhus University
  •  86
    The atomic number revolution in chemistry: a Kuhnian analysis
    Foundations of Chemistry 20 (3): 209-217. 2017.
    This paper argues that the field of chemistry underwent a significant change of theory in the early twentieth century, when atomic number replaced atomic weight as the principle for ordering and identifying the chemical elements. It is a classic case of a Kuhnian revolution. In the process of addressing anomalies, chemists who were trained to see elements as defined by their atomic weight discovered that their theoretical assumptions were impediments to understanding the chemical world. The only…Read more
  •  7
    Reflections on the origins and importance of our fields
    with Luciano Boschiero
    Metascience 26 (3): 353-354. 2017.
    This is an editorial.
  •  20
    Metascience is on the move
    with Luciano Boschiero
    Metascience 26 (2): 173-174. 2017.
    This is an editorial.
  •  99
    Kuhn’s Social Epistemology and the Sociology of Science
    In William J. Devlin & Alisa Bokulich (eds.), Kuhn’s Structure of Scientific Revolutions - 50 Years On, Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science, Vol. 311. Springer. pp. 167-183. 2015.
    This chapter discusses Kuhn’s conception of the history of science by focussing on two respects in which Kuhn is an historicist historian and philosopher of science. I identify two distinct, but related, aspects of historicism in the work of Hegel and show how these are also found in Kuhn’s work. First, Kuhn held tradition to be important for understanding scientific change and that the tradition from which a scientific idea originates must be understood in evaluating that idea. This makes Kuhn …Read more
  •  244
    I argue that van Fraassen’s selectionist explanation for the success of science is superior to the realists’ explanation. Whereas realists argue that our current theories are successful because they accurately reflect the structure of the world, the selectionist claims that our current theories are successful because unsuccessful theories have been eliminated. I argue that, unlike the explanation proposed by the realist, the selectionist explanation can also account for the failures of once succ…Read more
  •  98
    Scientific authorship in the age of collaborative research
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 37 (3): 505-514. 2006.
    I examine two challenges that collaborative research raises for science. First, collaborative research threatens the motivation of scientists. As a result, I argue, collaborative research may have adverse effects on what sorts of things scientists can effectively investigate. Second, collaborative research makes it more difficult to hold scientists accountable. I argue that the authors of multi-authored articles are aptly described as plural subjects, corporate bodies that are more than the sum …Read more
  •  169
    By means of a citation analysis I aim to determine which scholarly journals are most important in the sub-field of philosophy of science. My analysis shows that the six most important journals in the sub-field are Philosophy of Science , British Journal for the Philosophy of Science , Journal of Philosophy , Synthese , Studies in History and Philosophy of Science , and Erkenntnis . Given the data presented in this study, there is little evidence that there is such a field as the history and phil…Read more
  •  1
    Meaning and Convention and the Sociology of Science
    Eidos: The Canadian Graduate Journal of Philosophy 15 (2): 57-67. 1998.
  • The Role of Community in Inquiry: A Philosophical Study
    Dissertation, The University of Western Ontario (Canada). 1997.
    I examine a number of recent challenges to traditional individualist epistemologies. In chapter I, I examine Margaret Gilbert's claim that certain types of communities, "plural subjects," are capable of having what she calls "collective beliefs." In chapter II, I examine Lynn Hankinson Nelson's claim that communities, and not individuals, are the primary epistemological agents. In chapter III, I examine Miriam Solomon's claim that scientific rationality is a property of communities, not individu…Read more
  •  13
    A look behind the curtain: the editorial board
    with Luciano Boschiero
    Metascience 25 (3): 341-342. 2016.
    This is an editorial.
  •  141
    The argument from underconsideration as grounds for anti‐realism: A defence
    International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 22 (3). 2008.
    The anti-realist argument from underconsideration focuses on the fact that, when scientists evaluate theories, they only ever consider a subset of the theories that can account for the available data. As a result, when scientists judge one theory to be superior to competitor theories, they are not warranted in drawing the conclusion that the superior theory is likely true with respect to what it says about unobservable entities and processes. I defend the argument from underconsideration from th…Read more
  •  8
    Editorial
    with Luciano Boschiero
    Metascience 24 (1): 1-2. 2015.
    Last year Stathis and Theodore approached us about taking on the editorship of Metascience, as their 5 year term was coming to an end. We were greatly honoured but also overcome with trepidation. Metascience has become an important source for keeping abreast of the most recent books published in the history, sociology and philosophy of science. And the number of reviews published in the journal each year is prodigious. Further, it has been run with thoughtfulness and great care since its beginni…Read more
  •  120
    Pessimistic Inductions: Four Varieties
    International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 29 (1): 61-73. 2015.
    The pessimistic induction plays an important role in the contemporary realism/anti-realism debate in philosophy of science. But there is some disagreement about the structure and aim of the argument. And a number of scholars have noted that there is more than one type of PI in the philosophical literature. I review four different versions of the PI. I aim to show that PIs have been appealed to by philosophers of science for a variety of reasons. Even some realists have appealed to a PI. My goal …Read more
  •  24
    Rethinking Scientific Specialization
    Social Studies of Science 35 (1): 151-164. 2005.
    My aim in this paper is to re-examine specialization in science. I argue that we need to acknowledge the role that conceptual changes can play in the creation of new specialties. Whereas earlier sociological accounts focus on social and instrumental changes as the cause of the creation of new specialties, I argue that conceptual changes play an important role in the creation of some scientific specialties. Specifically, I argue that conceptual developments played an important role in the creatio…Read more
  •  24
    Knowledge and Inquiry: Readings in Epistemology (edited book)
    Broadview Press. 2002.
    This anthology focuses on three areas in the theory of knowledge: epistemic justification; analyses of knowledge and scepticism; and recent development in epistemology. Each of the three sections includes a brief introduction to the readings, a series of study questions, and a list of suggested readings. Section 1 deals with coherentism, foundationalism, reliabilism, and includes articles by Chisholm, BonJour, Audi, Goldman, and Fumerton. Section 2 deals with the analysis of knowledge and Gettie…Read more
  •  164
    Epistemic Privilege and the Success of Science
    Noûs 46 (3): 375-385. 2010.
    Realists and anti-realists disagree about whether contemporary scientists are epistemically privileged. Because the issue of epistemic privilege figures in arguments in support of and against theoretical knowledge in science, it is worth examining whether or not there is any basis for assuming such privilege. I show that arguments that try to explain the success of science by appeal to some sort of epistemic privilege have, so far, failed. They have failed to give us reason to believe (i) that s…Read more
  •  1616
    The epistemic significance of collaborative research
    Philosophy of Science 69 (1): 150-168. 2002.
    I examine the epistemic import of collaborative research in science. I develop and defend a functional explanation for its growing importance. Collaborative research is becoming more popular in the natural sciences, and to a lesser degree in the social sciences, because contemporary research in these fields frequently requires access to abundant resources, for which there is great competition. Scientists involved in collaborative research have been very successful in accessing these resources, w…Read more
  •  12
    Book Reviews (review)
    International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 19 (2): 213-222. 2005.
  •  41
    Social epistemology
    In Stathis Psillos & Martin Curd (eds.), The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Science, Routledge. 2013.
    Social epistemology is a wide-ranging field of study concerned with investigating how various social factors, practices, and institutions affect our prospects of gaining and spreading knowledge. Philosophers working in social epistemology have focused on a range of topics, including trust and testimony, the effects of social location on knowing, and whether or not groups of people can have knowledge that is not reducible to the knowledge of the individual members of the group. Much of the work i…Read more
  •  62
    The methodological defense of realism scrutinized
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 54 74-79. 2015.
    I revisit an older defense of scientific realism, the methodological defense, a defense developed by both Popper and Feyerabend. The methodological defense of realism concerns the attitude of scientists, not philosophers of science. The methodological defense is as follows: a commitment to realism leads scientists to pursue the truth, which in turn is apt to put them in a better position to get at the truth. In contrast, anti-realists lack the tenacity required to develop a theory to its fullest…Read more
  •  16
    Metascience and Neurath’s boat
    with Luciano Boschiero
    Metascience 24 (2): 171-172. 2015.
    Otto Neurath compared science to a ship at sea on which the sailors have to repair their vessel as they keep it afloat. Metascience is a ship of a similar sort. Do not worry. There are no repairs to report. But changes are being made at Metascience on an ongoing basis, even as we work to meet our production deadlines. With this, our second issue, we would like to announce some further changes with the journal.Ties Nijseen and Christi Lue who have long been responsible for many of the matters rel…Read more
  •  60
    COLLABORATIVE RESEARCH, DELIBERATION, AND INNOVATION
    Episteme 11 (3): 291-303. 2014.
    I evaluate the extent to which we could learn something about how we should be conducting collaborative research in science from the research on groupthink. I argue that Solomon has set us in the wrong direction, failing to recognize that the consensus in scientific specialties is not the result of deliberation. But the attention to the structure of problem-solving that has emerged in the groupthink research conducted by psychologists can help us see when deliberation could lead to problems for …Read more
  •  1014
    Invisible hands and the success of science
    Philosophy of Science 67 (1): 163-175. 2000.
    David Hull accounts for the success of science in terms of an invisible hand mechanism, arguing that it is difficult to reconcile scientists' self-interestedness or their desire for recognition with traditional philosophical explanations for the success of science. I argue that we have less reason to invoke an invisible hand mechanism to explain the success of science than Hull implies, and that many of the practices and institutions constitutive of science are intentionally designed by scientis…Read more
  • David L. Hull, Science and Selection: Essays on Biological Evolution and the Philosophy of Science (review)
    International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 16 (2): 191-192. 2002.
    This is a book review of David Hull's edited volume of collected papers, Science and Selection.
  •  133
    Who has scientific knowledge?
    Social Epistemology 21 (3). 2007.
    I examine whether or not it is apt to attribute knowledge to groups of scientists. I argue that though research teams can be aptly described as having knowledge, communities of scientists identified with research fields, and the scientific community as a whole are not capable of knowing. Scientists involved in research teams are dependent on each other, and are organized in a manner to advance a goal. Such teams also adopt views that may not be identical to the views of the individual members of…Read more
  •  14
    Exciting days
    with Luciano Boschiero
    Metascience 26 (1): 1-2. 2017.
    This is an editorial.
  •  35
    This is a review of Paul Hoyningen-Huene's book, Systematicity: The Nature of Science.