K. Brad Wray

Aarhus University
  •  88
    The atomic number revolution in chemistry: a Kuhnian analysis
    Foundations of Chemistry 20 (3): 209-217. 2017.
    This paper argues that the field of chemistry underwent a significant change of theory in the early twentieth century, when atomic number replaced atomic weight as the principle for ordering and identifying the chemical elements. It is a classic case of a Kuhnian revolution. In the process of addressing anomalies, chemists who were trained to see elements as defined by their atomic weight discovered that their theoretical assumptions were impediments to understanding the chemical world. The only…Read more
  •  7
    Reflections on the origins and importance of our fields
    with Luciano Boschiero
    Metascience 26 (3): 353-354. 2017.
    This is an editorial.
  •  20
    Metascience is on the move
    with Luciano Boschiero
    Metascience 26 (2): 173-174. 2017.
    This is an editorial.
  •  100
    Kuhn’s Social Epistemology and the Sociology of Science
    In William J. Devlin & Alisa Bokulich (eds.), Kuhn’s Structure of Scientific Revolutions - 50 Years On, Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science, Vol. 311. Springer. pp. 167-183. 2015.
    This chapter discusses Kuhn’s conception of the history of science by focussing on two respects in which Kuhn is an historicist historian and philosopher of science. I identify two distinct, but related, aspects of historicism in the work of Hegel and show how these are also found in Kuhn’s work. First, Kuhn held tradition to be important for understanding scientific change and that the tradition from which a scientific idea originates must be understood in evaluating that idea. This makes Kuhn …Read more
  •  246
    I argue that van Fraassen’s selectionist explanation for the success of science is superior to the realists’ explanation. Whereas realists argue that our current theories are successful because they accurately reflect the structure of the world, the selectionist claims that our current theories are successful because unsuccessful theories have been eliminated. I argue that, unlike the explanation proposed by the realist, the selectionist explanation can also account for the failures of once succ…Read more
  •  99
    Scientific authorship in the age of collaborative research
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 37 (3): 505-514. 2006.
    I examine two challenges that collaborative research raises for science. First, collaborative research threatens the motivation of scientists. As a result, I argue, collaborative research may have adverse effects on what sorts of things scientists can effectively investigate. Second, collaborative research makes it more difficult to hold scientists accountable. I argue that the authors of multi-authored articles are aptly described as plural subjects, corporate bodies that are more than the sum …Read more
  •  172
    By means of a citation analysis I aim to determine which scholarly journals are most important in the sub-field of philosophy of science. My analysis shows that the six most important journals in the sub-field are Philosophy of Science , British Journal for the Philosophy of Science , Journal of Philosophy , Synthese , Studies in History and Philosophy of Science , and Erkenntnis . Given the data presented in this study, there is little evidence that there is such a field as the history and phil…Read more
  •  1
    Meaning and Convention and the Sociology of Science
    Eidos: The Canadian Graduate Journal of Philosophy 15 (2): 57-67. 1998.
  •  2
    Does science have a moving target?
    American Philosophical Quarterly 42 (1): 47-58. 2005.
    Kuhn argues that science does not aim at the truth. Alexander Bird raises concerns form Kuhn's view. I defend Kuhn's claim and argue that insofar as science has a goal it is a moving target.
  •  4
    WH Newton-Smith, ed., A Companion to the Philosophy of Science Reviewed (review)
    Philosophy in Review 22 (2): 136-128. 2002.
  •  15
    Metascience: reflections on the symposium
    with Luciano Boschiero
    Metascience 25 (2): 161-162. 2016.
    This is an editorial.
  •  39
    This is a book review of Markku Peltonen's edited volume, The Cambridge Companion to Bacon, a collection of papers on the philosophy of Francis Bacon.
  •  22
    I examine the degree of specialization in various sub-fields of philosophy, drawing on data from the PhilPapers Survey. The following three sub-fields are highly specialized: Ancient philosophy, seventeenth/eighteenth century philosophy, and philosophy of physics. The following sub-fields have a low level of specialization: metaphilosophy, philosophy of religion, philosophy of probability, philosophy of the social sciences, decision theory, and philosophy of race and gender. Highly specialized s…Read more
  •  76
    Systematicity and the Continuity Thesis
    Synthese 196 (3): 819-832. 2019.
    Hoyningen-Huene develops an account of what science is, distinguishing it from common sense. According to Hoyningen-Huene, the key distinguishing feature is that science is more systematic. He identifies nine ways in which science is more systematic than common sense. I compare Hoyningen-Huene’s view to a view I refer to as the “Continuity Thesis.” The Continuity Thesis states that scientific knowledge is just an extension of common sense. This thesis is associated with Quine, Planck, and others…Read more
  •  10
    Kuhn's constructionism
    Perspectives on Science 18 (3): 311-327. 2010.
    I challenge Hacking's characterization of Kuhn's constructionism. I argue that Kuhn does not believe that nature has no joints. Rather, Kuhn believes there is no unique correct way to cut nature into kinds. I also argue that Kuhn is not an externalist. He believes that disputes in science are resolved on the basis of a consideration of the epistemic merits of the theories. Subjective factors merely ensure that competing theories are developed, and the strengths and weaknesses of the theories are…Read more
  •  21
  •  149
    A defense of Longino's social epistemology
    Philosophy of Science 66 (3): 552. 1999.
    Though many agree that we need to account for the role that social factors play in inquiry, developing a viable social epistemology has proved to be difficult. According to Longino, it is the processes that make inquiry possible that are aptly described as "social," for they require a number of people to sustain them. These processes, she claims, not only facilitate inquiry, but also ensure that the results of inquiry are more than mere subjective opinions, and thus deserve to be called "knowled…Read more
  •  4
    The role of solidarity in a pragmatic epistemology
    Philosophia 27 (1-2): 273-286. 1999.
    I critically examine Rorty's social epistemology, specifically his claim that the end of inquiry is solidarity.
  •  11
    David Oldroyd 1936–2014
    with Luciano Boschiero
    Metascience 24 (1): 3-4. 2015.
    David Oldroyd died in Sydney on 7 November 2014. Many readers of this journal would know of David’s impressive career as an historian of science and many would have also had the pleasure of knowing David personally. His academic career spanned across England, New Zealand and Australia, and his expertise in history of geology took him to several parts of the world for conferences and research, archival as well as geological, including Europe, China, Turkey, Russia and North America. His experienc…Read more
  •  1
    Shapin's the scientific revolution: What will philosophers find? (review)
    Social Epistemology 13 (3 & 4). 1999.
    This is a book review of Steven Shapin's The Scientific Revolution.
  •  23
    We examine the sub-field of philosophy of science using a new method developed in information science, Referenced Publication Years Spectroscopy (RPYS). RPYS allows us to identify peak years in citations in a field, which promises to help scholars identify the key contributions to a field, and revolutionary discoveries in a field. We discovered that philosophy of science, a sub-field in the humanities, differs significantly from other fields examined with this method. Books play a more important…Read more
  •  1
    James Robert Brown, Who Rules in Science?: An Opinionated Guide to the Wars Reviewed (review)
    Philosophy in Review 23 (2): 84-86. 2003.
    A critical examination of James Brown's Who Rules in Science?
  •  88
    Discarded theories: the role of changing interests
    Synthese 196 (2): 553-569. 2019.
    I take another look at the history of science and offer some fresh insights into why the history of science is filled with discarded theories. I argue that the history of science is just as we should expect it to be, given the following two facts about science: theories are always only partial representations of the world, and almost inevitably scientists will be led to investigate phenomena that the accepted theory is not fit to account for. Together these facts suggest that most scientific the…Read more
  •  12
    Supporting the “metascientific” community
    with Luciano Boschiero
    Metascience 24 (3): 341-342. 2015.
    This is an editorial.
  •  9
    I compare the epistemic culture of Wikipedia with the epistemic culture of science, with special attention to the culture of collaborative research in science. The two cultures differ markedly with respect to (1) the knowledge produced, (2) who produces the knowledge, and (3) the processes by which knowledge is produced. Wikipedia has created a community of inquirers that are governed by norms very different from those that govern scientists. Those who contribute to Wikipedia do not ground their…Read more
  •  77
    The Influence of James B. Conant on Kuhn’s Structure of Scientific Revolutions
    Hopos: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 6 (1): 1-23. 2016.
    I examine the influence of James B. Conant on the writing of Kuhn’s Structure of Scientific Revolutions. By clarifying Conant’s influence on Kuhn, I also clarify the influence that others had on Kuhn’s thinking. And by identifying the various influences that Conant had on Kuhn’s view of science, I identify Kuhn’s most original contributions in Structure. On the one hand, I argue that much of the framework and many of the concepts that figure in Structure were part of Conant’s picture of science,…Read more
  •  89
    Science, biases, and the threat of global pessimism
    Proceedings of the Philosophy of Science Association 2001 (3). 2001.
    Philip Kitcher rejects the global pessimists' view that the conclusions reached in inquiry are determined by the interests of some segment of the population, arguing that only some inquiries, for example, inquiries into race and gender, are adversely affected by interests. I argue that the biases Kitcher believes affect such inquiries are operative in all domains, but the prevalence of such biases does not support global pessimism. I argue further that in order to address the global pessimists' …Read more