•  11
    Kant and Skepticism (review)
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 47 (2): 319-320. 2009.
    Kant's theoretical philosophy is often read as a response to skeptical challenges raised by his predecessors. Yet Kant himself explicitly discusses skepticism in relatively few places in his published work, so Michael Forster's focused examination of Kant's relation to skepticism is a useful addition to the literature. Forster sets out to distinguish different types of skepticism to which Kant might be responding, determine what responses Kant offers, and evaluate the strength of those responses…Read more
  •  4107
    Kant’s transcendental idealism hinges on a distinction between appearances and things in themselves. The debate about how to understand this distinction has largely ignored the way that Kant applies this distinction to the self. I argue that this is a mistake, and that Kant’s acceptance of a single, unified self in both his theoretical and practical philosophy causes serious problems for the ‘two-world’ interpretation of his idealism.
  •  310
    Skorupski, John., The Domain of Reasons (review)
    Review of Metaphysics 66 (4): 852-854. 2013.
  •  3272
    Does Kant Demand Explanations for All Synthetic A Priori Claims?
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 52 (3): 549-576. 2014.
    Kant's philosophy promises to explain various synthetic a priori claims. Yet, as several of his commentators have noted, it is hard to see how these explanations could work unless they themselves rested on unexplained synthetic a priori claims. Since Kant appears to demand explanations for all synthetic a priori claims, it would seem that his project fails on its own terms. I argue, however, that Kant holds that explanations are required only for synthetic a priori claims about (purportedly) exp…Read more
  •  280
    The Mind and the Body as 'One and the Same Thing' in Spinoza
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 17 (5): 897-919. 2009.
    I argue that, contrary to how he is often read, Spinoza did not believe that the mind and the body were numerically identical. This means that we must find some alternative reading for his claims that they are 'one and the same thing'
  •  249
    Kant's Metaphysics of the Self
    Philosophers' Imprint 10 1-21. 2010.
    I argue that Kant's Critique of Pure Reason offers a positive metaphysical account of the thinking self. Previous interpreters have overlooked this account, I believe, because they have held that any metaphysical view of the self would be incompatible with both Kant's insistence on the limitations of cognition and with his project in the Paralogisms. Closer examination, however, shows that neither of those aspects of the Critique precludes a metaphysical account of the self, and that other aspec…Read more
  •  549
    Lockean Empathy
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 54 (1): 87-106. 2016.
    This paper offers an epistemic defense of empathy, drawing on John Locke's theory of ideas. Locke held that ideas of shape, unlike ideas of color, had a distinctive value: resembling qualities in their objects. I argue that the same is true of empathy, as when someone is pained by someone's pain. This means that empathy has the same epistemic value or objectivity that Locke and other early modern philosophers assigned to veridical perceptions of shape. For this to hold, pain and pleasure must be…Read more
  •  21
    Review: Ameriks, Karl, Kant's Elliptical Path (review)
    Philosophy in Review 34 (1-2): 1-3. 2014.