•  403
    Graded Causation and Defaults
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 66 (2): 413-457. 2015.
    Recent work in psychology and experimental philosophy has shown that judgments of actual causation are often influenced by consideration of defaults, typicality, and normality. A number of philosophers and computer scientists have also suggested that an appeal to such factors can help deal with problems facing existing accounts of actual causation. This article develops a flexible formal framework for incorporating defaults, typicality, and normality into an account of actual causation. The resu…Read more
  •  78
    Updating Probability: Tracking Statistics as Criterion
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science. 2016.
    ABSTRACT For changing opinion, represented by an assignment of probabilities to propositions, the criterion proposed is motivated by the requirement that the assignment should have, and maintain, the possibility of matching in some appropriate sense statistical proportions in a population. This ‘tracking’ criterion implies limitations on policies for updating in response to a wide range of types of new input. Satisfying the criterion is shown equivalent to the principle that the prior must be a …Read more
  •  85
    Compact Representations of Extended Causal Models
    Cognitive Science 37 (6): 986-1010. 2013.
    Judea Pearl (2000) was the first to propose a definition of actual causation using causal models. A number of authors have suggested that an adequate account of actual causation must appeal not only to causal structure but also to considerations of normality. In Halpern and Hitchcock (2011), we offer a definition of actual causation using extended causal models, which include information about both causal structure and normality. Extended causal models are potentially very complex. In this study…Read more
  •  99
    Reasoning about knowledge
    with Ronald Fagin, Yoram Moses, and Moshe Vardi
    MIT Press. 2003.
    Reasoning About Knowledge is the first book to provide a general discussion of approaches to reasoning about knowledge and its applications to distributed ...
  •  2
    Causality, Probability, and Heuristics: A Tribute to Judea Pearl
    with Christopher Hitchcock
    College Publications. 2010.
  •  30
    Sufficient conditions for causality to be transitive
    Philosophy of Science 83 (2): 213-226. 2016.
    Natural conditions are provided that are sufficient to ensure that causality as defined by approaches that use counterfactual dependence and structural equations will be transitive.
  •  21
    Actual Causality
    MIT Press. 2016.
    A new approach for defining causality and such related notions as degree of responsibility, degrees of blame, and causal explanation. Causality plays a central role in the way people structure the world; we constantly seek causal explanations for our observations. But what does it even mean that an event C "actually caused" event E? The problem of defining actual causation goes beyond mere philosophical speculation. For example, in many legal arguments, it is precisely what needs to be establish…Read more
  •  122
    Causes and Explanations: A Structural-Model Approach. Part II: Explanations
    with Judea Pearl
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 56 (4): 889-911. 2005.
    We propose new definitions of (causal) explanation, using structural equations to model counterfactuals. The definition is based on the notion of actual cause, as defined and motivated in a companion article. Essentially, an explanation is a fact that is not known for certain but, if found to be true, would constitute an actual cause of the fact to be explained, regardless of the agent's initial uncertainty. We show that the definition handles well a number of problematic examples from the liter…Read more
  •  67
    I'm OK if you're OK: On the notion of trusting communication (review)
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 17 (4). 1988.
    We consider the issue of what an agent or a processor needs to know in order to know that its messages are true. This may be viewed as a first step to a general theory of cooperative communication in distributed systems. An honest message is one that is known to be true when it is sent (or said). If every message that is sent is honest, then of course every message that is sent is true. Various weaker considerations than honesty are investigated with the property that provided every message sent…Read more
  •  23
    Zero-one laws for modal logic
    with Joseph Y. Halpern and Bruce Kapron
    Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 69 (2-3): 157-193. 1994.
    We show that a 0–1 law holds for propositional modal logic, both for structure validity and frame validity. In the case of structure validity, the result follows easily from the well-known 0–1 law for first-order logic. However, our proof gives considerably more information. It leads to an elegant axiomatization for almost-sure structure validity and to sharper complexity bounds. Since frame validity can be reduced to a Π11 formula, the 0–1 law for frame validity helps delineate when 0–1 laws ex…Read more
  •  85
    Reasoning About Uncertainty
    MIT Press. 2003.
    Using formal systems to represent and reason about uncertainty.
  •  80
    On definability in multimodal logic
    with Dov Samet and Ella Segev
    Review of Symbolic Logic 2 (3): 451-468. 2009.
    Three notions of definability in multimodal logic are considered. Two are analogous to the notions of explicit definability and implicit definability introduced by Beth in the context of first-order logic. However, while by Beth’s theorem the two types of definability are equivalent for first-order logic, such an equivalence does not hold for multimodal logics. A third notion of definability, reducibility, is introduced; it is shown that in multimodal logics, explicit definability is equivalent …Read more
  • First-order conditional logic for default reasoning revisited
    with Nir Friedman, Koller Y., and Daphne
    Acm Trans. Comput. Logic 1 (2): 175--207. 2000.
  •  52
    Taken by surprise: The paradox of the surprise test revisited (review)
    with Yoram Moses
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 15 (3). 1986.
    A teacher announced to his pupils that on exactly one of the days of the following school week (Monday through Friday) he would give them a test. But it would be a surprise test; on the evening before the test they would not know that the test would take place the next day. One of the brighter students in the class then argued that the teacher could never give them the test. "It can't be Friday," she said, "since in that case we'll expect it on Thurday evening. But then it can't be Thursday, sin…Read more
  •  52
    Presburger arithmetic with unary predicates is Π11 complete
    Journal of Symbolic Logic 56 (2). 1991.
    We give a simple proof characterizing the complexity of Presburger arithmetic augmented with additional predicates. We show that Presburger arithmetic with additional predicates is Π 1 1 complete. Adding one unary predicate is enough to get Π 1 1 hardness, while adding more predicates (of any arity) does not make the complexity any worse
  •  45
    Intransitivity and vagueness - corrigendum
    Review of Symbolic Logic 2 (3): 591-591. 2009.
    doi: 10.1017/S1755020308090084, Published by Cambridge University Press 31 March 2009 in Volume 1, Number 4 of The Review of Symbolic Logic . On page 541, in the 4 th paragraph, in line 7, an error occurred. The sentence should correctly read: “For all worlds w , if there is more than one grain of sand in the pile in w , then there is still more than one grain of sand after removing one grain of sand.”
  •  57
    Reasoning about Knowledge: A Response by the Authors (review)
    with Ronald Fagin, Yoram Moses, and Moshe Y. Vardi
    Minds and Machines 7 (1): 113-113. 1997.
  •  12
    The bottleneck may be the solution, not the problem
    with Arnon Lotem, Oren Kolodny, Luca Onnis, and Shimon Edelman
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 39. 2016.
  •  45
    On the unusual effectiveness of logic in computer science
    with Robert Harper, Neil Immerman, Phokion G. Kolaitis, Moshe Y. Vardi, and Victor Vianu
    Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 7 (2): 213-236. 2001.
    In 1960, E. P. Wigner, a joint winner of the 1963 Nobel Prize for Physics, published a paper titled On the Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics in the Natural Sciences [61]. This paper can be construed as an examination and affirmation of Galileo's tenet that “The book of nature is written in the language of mathematics”. To this effect, Wigner presented a large number of examples that demonstrate the effectiveness of mathematics in accurately describing physical phenomena. Wigner viewed th…Read more
  •  57
    Evidence with uncertain likelihoods
    with Riccardo Pucella
    Synthese 171 (1): 111-133. 2009.
    An agent often has a number of hypotheses, and must choose among them based on observations, or outcomes of experiments. Each of these observations can be viewed as providing evidence for or against various hypotheses. All the attempts to formalize this intuition up to now have assumed that associated with each hypothesis h there is a likelihood function  μ h , which is a probability measure that intuitively describes how likely each observation is, conditional on h being the correct hypothesis.…Read more
  •  283
    Asymptotic conditional probabilities: The non-unary case
    with Adam J. Grove and Daphne Koller
    Journal of Symbolic Logic 61 (1): 250-276. 1996.
    Motivated by problems that arise in computing degrees of belief, we consider the problem of computing asymptotic conditional probabilities for first-order sentences. Given first-order sentences φ and θ, we consider the structures with domain {1,..., N} that satisfy θ, and compute the fraction of them in which φ is true. We then consider what happens to this fraction as N gets large. This extends the work on 0-1 laws that considers the limiting probability of first-order sentences, by considering…Read more
  •  90
    Great Expectations. Part I: On the Customizability of Generalized Expected Utility (review)
    with Francis C. Chu
    Theory and Decision 64 (1): 1-36. 2008.
    We propose a generalization of expected utility that we call generalized EU (GEU), where a decision maker’s beliefs are represented by plausibility measures and the decision maker’s tastes are represented by general (i.e., not necessarily real-valued) utility functions. We show that every agent, “rational” or not, can be modeled as a GEU maximizer. We then show that we can customize GEU by selectively imposing just the constraints we want. In particular, we show how each of Savage’s postulates c…Read more
  •  99
    The Role of the Protocol in Anthropic Reasoning
    Ergo: An Open Access Journal of Philosophy 2 195-206. 2015.
    I show how thinking in terms of the protocol used can help clarify problems related to anthropic reasoning and self-location, such as the Doomsday Argument and the Sleeping Beauty Problem.
  •  406
    Minimizing regret in dynamic decision problems
    with Samantha Leung
    Theory and Decision 81 (1): 123-151. 2016.
    The menu-dependent nature of regret-minimization creates subtleties when it is applied to dynamic decision problems. It is not clear whether forgone opportunities should be included in the menu. We explain commonly observed behavioral patterns as minimizing regret when forgone opportunities are present. If forgone opportunities are included, we can characterize when a form of dynamic consistency is guaranteed.