•  39
    Otto Neurath: Philosophy between Science and Politics (review)
    with Nancy Cartwright, Jordi Cat, Lola Fleck, and Thomas E. Uebel
    Philosophical Review 107 (2): 327. 1998.
    Four distinguished authors have been brought together to produce this elegant study of a much-neglected figure. The book is divided into three sections: Neurath's biographical background and the economic and social context of his ideas; his theory of science; and the development of his role in debates on Marxist concepts of history and his own conception of science. Coinciding with the emerging serious interest in logical positivism, this timely publication will redress a current imbalance in th…Read more
  •  46
    Invariance Principles as Regulative Ideals: From Wigner to Hilbert: Thomas Ryckman
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 63 63-80. 2008.
    Eugene Wigner's several general discussions of symmetry and invariance principles are among the canonical texts of contemporary philosophy of physics. Wigner spoke from a position of authority, having pioneered for recognition of the importance of symmetry principles from nuclear to molecular physics. But perhaps recent commentators have not sufficiently stressed that Wigner always took care to situate the notion of invariance principles with respect to two others, initial conditions and laws of…Read more
  •  60
    Metaphysics Avoidance: Mark Wilson and Ernst Cassirer
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 103 (2): 466-472. 2021.
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Volume 103, Issue 2, Page 466-472, September 2021.
  •  94
    In early major works, Cassirer and Schlick differently recast traditional doctrines of the concept and of the relation of concept to intuitive content along the lines of recent epistemological discussions within the exact sciences. In this, they attempted to refashion epistemology by incorporating as its basic principle the notion of functional coordination, the theoretical sciences' own methodological tool for dispensing with the imprecise and unreliable guide of intuitive evidence. Examining t…Read more
  •  65
    Chaos, Clio, and Scientistic Illusions of Understanding
    History and Theory 34 (1): 30-44. 1995.
    A number of authors have recently argued that the mathematical insights of "chaos theory" offer a promising formal model or significant analogy for understanding at least some historical events. We examine a representative claim of each kind regarding the application of chaos theory to problems of historical explanation. We identify two lines of argument. One we term the Causal Thesis, which states that chaos theory may be used to plausibly model, and so explain, historical events. The other we …Read more
  •  175
    Recently discovered correspondence from Oskar Becker to Hermann Weyl sheds new light on Weyl's engagement with Husserlian transcendental phenomenology in 1918-1927. Here the last two of these letters, dated July and August, 1926, dealing with issues in the philosophy of mathematics are presented, together with background and a detailed commentary. The letters provide an instructive context for re-assessing the connection between intuitionism and phenomenology in Weyl's foundational thought, and …Read more
  •  23
    Philosophy of Science and its Discontents
    Noûs 27 (2): 261-264. 1993.
  •  183
    Hilbert's 'foundations of physics': Gravitation and electromagnetism within the axiomatic method
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 39 (1): 102-153. 2008.
  •  10
    Hilbert on General Covariance and Causality
    In David E. Rowe, Tilman Sauer & Scott A. Walter (eds.), Beyond Einstein: Perspectives on Geometry, Gravitation, and Cosmology in the Twentieth Century, Springer New York. pp. 67-77. 2018.
    Einstein and Hilbert both struggled to reconcile general covariance and causality in their early work on general relativity. In Einstein’s case, this first led to his infamous “hole argument”, a stumbling block that persuaded him early on that generally covariant field equations for gravitation could never be found. After his breakthrough to general covariance in the fall of 1915, the resolution came in form of the “point-coincidence argument.” Hilbert from the beginning took a different view of…Read more
  •  8
    Book Reviews (review)
    with Doohwan Ahn, Nataša Bakić-Mirić, Giorgio Baruchello, Cristina M. Bettin, Martine Benjamin, Michael Bonura, Peter Burke, Camelia Mihaela Cmeciu, John M. Cox, Janina K. Darling, Donald J. Dietrich, Liviu Drugus, Daphna Erdinast-Vulcan, Steven L. Goldman, Boris Gubman, Grant Havers, Stefan Höjelid, Javier A. Ibáñez-Noé, Horst Jesse, Rachael Lorna Johnstone, Steven Joyce, Yves Laberge, David W. Lovell, Joseph Mali, Glenn W. Olsen, Bruce F. Pauley, Duncan Richter, Sheldon Rothblatt, Arthur B. Shostak, Stanley Shostak, Barnard Turner, Timothy Unwin, Frederick G. Whelan, and Warren C. Wood
    The European Legacy 13 (7): 877-916. 2008.
  •  43
    Einstein, Cassirer, and General Covariance — Then and Now
    Science in Context 12 (4): 585-619. 1999.
    The ArgumentRecent archival research has brought about a new understanding of the import of Einstein's puzzling remarks (1916) attributing a physical meaning to general covariance. Debates over the scope and meaning of general covariance still persist, even within physics. But already in 1921 Cassirer identified the significance of general covariance as a novel stage in the development of the criterion of objectivity within physics; an account of this development, and its implications, is the pr…Read more
  •  49
    Weyl, Reichenbach and the epistemology of geometry
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 25 (6): 831-870. 1994.
  • What Carnap Might Have Learned from Weyl
    In Christian Damböck (ed.), Influences on the Aufbau, Springer Verlag. 2016.
  • This work examines the foundations of linguistic theory, with particular reference to the status and justification of grammars and theories of language structure. A metatheoretical critique of generative grammar is followed by epistemological motivation for, and presentation of, an alternative conception of language structure due to Harris, together with an approach to its justification. It is proposed that grammars have an informational validity as structures comprised of maximally unredundant …Read more
  •  29
  •  8
    Otto Neurath (review)
    Philosophical Review 107 (2): 327-329. 1998.
    This collaborative work provides an intellectual portrait of a man known to most students of philosophy today only as a lesser founding member of the Vienna Circle. It makes a strong case for the intrinsic interest and continuing relevance of much of Neurath’s thought to contemporary science studies, considered broadly. Together with several other recent works on Neurath, it forces a substantial revision in any assessment of the Vienna Circle and its legacy. Finally, it describes, in some detail…Read more
  •  60
    On believing, saying and expressing
    Synthese 79 (2). 1989.
    Examines the connections among believing, saying, and expressing in situations where the sentence used is a declarative sentence containing at least one proper name. Proposes a new way of understanding these connections. Develops an argument for the thesis that, although we typically believe the singular propositions expressed by our uses of name sentences, we rarely use such sentences because we believe those propositions.
  •  18
    Book reviews (review)
    Mind 101 (402): 397-401. 1992.
  •  54
    Belief, linguistic behavior, and propositional content
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 47 (2): 277-287. 1986.
  •  75
    Contingency, a prioricity and acquaintance
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 53 (2): 323-343. 1993.
  •  36
    Dickie on artifactuality
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 47 (2): 175-177. 1989.