Saint Louis University
Department of Philosophy
PhD, 1977
College Station, Texas, United States of America
Areas of Specialization
17th/18th Century Philosophy
  •  438
    Berkeley's Rejection of Divine Analogy
    Science Et Esprit 63 (2): 149-161. 2011.
    Berkeley argues that claims about divine predication (e.g., God is wise or exists) should be understood literally rather than analogically, because like all spirits (i.e., causes), God is intelligible only in terms of the extent of his effects. By focusing on the harmony and order of nature, Berkeley thus unites his view of God with his doctrines of mind, force, grace, and power, and avoids challenges to religious claims that are raised by appeals to analogy. The essay concludes by showing how a…Read more
  •  29
    Paramodern Strategies of Philosophical Historiography
    Epoché: A Journal for the History of Philosophy 1 (1): 41-63. 1993.
  •  28
    A philosophical theory of literary continuity and change
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 18 (3): 275-280. 1980.
  •  35
    Montréal Conference Summaries
    with Sébastien Charles
    Berkeley Studies 23 54-57. 2012.
    In June of 2012 scholars from Europe and North America met in Montreal to commemorate the 300th anniversary of the publication of George Berkeley's *Passive Obedience*. In this article Stephen Daniel summarizes the English presentations, and Sébastien Charles summarizes the French presentations, on how Berkeley invokes naturalistic themes in developing a moral theory while still allowing a role for God.
  •  34
    The Semiotic Ontology of Jonathan Edwards
    Modern Schoolman 71 (4): 285-304. 1994.
    Jonathan Edwards' marginalization in modern philosophy stems from his refusal to endorse the predicational logic and substantialist ontology of the rationalist-empiricist debate. Instead, he appeals to a communicative, semiotic logic of propositions grounded in Stoic thought and thematized by Peter Ramus and his Puritan followers. That alternative logic displays an "ontology of supposition" that guarantees God's existence, justifies typological, magical, and even astrological inferences, undermi…Read more
  •  8
    Incoming Editor’s Note
    Berkeley Studies 17 3. 2006.
    A quick introduction to my becoming the editor of *Berkeley Studies* in 2006.
  • The Nature of Light in Descartes' Physics
    Philosophical Forum 7 (3): 323. 1976.
  •  66
    Civility and sociability: Hobbes on man and citizen
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 18 (2): 209-215. 1980.
  •  22
    Berkeley: Philosophical Writings, ed. Desmond M. Clarke (review)
    Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2009 (7). 2009.
  •  552
    Berkeley's Doctrine of Mind and the “Black List Hypothesis”: A Dialogue
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 51 (1): 24-41. 2013.
    Clues about what Berkeley was planning to say about mind in his now-lost second volume of the Principles seem to abound in his Notebooks. However, commentators have been reluctant to use his unpublished entries to explicate his remarks about spiritual substances in the Principles and Dialogues for three reasons. First, it has proven difficult to reconcile the seemingly Humean bundle theory of the self in the Notebooks with Berkeley's published characterization of spirits as “active beings or pri…Read more
  •  67
    Preparations for a Research Paper in Philosophy
    Teaching Philosophy 3 (2): 185-188. 1979.
  • Ramist Dialectic in Leibniz's Early Thought
    In Mark Kulstad, Mogens Laerke & David Snyder (eds.), The philosophy of the young Leibniz, Steiner. pp. 59-66. 2009.
  •  14
    Myth and modern philosophy
    Temple University Press. 1990.
    A study of the historiographic significance and use of mythic or fabular thinking in Bacon, Descartes, Mandeville, Vico, Herder, and others.
  •  24
    An examination of Edwards’ ontology and his ideas on creation, God, sin, freedom, virtue, and beauty.
  •  16
    Hobbes and America (review)
    Review of Metaphysics 36 (3): 698-700. 1983.
  •  49
    Descartes on Myth and Ingenuity / Ingenium
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 23 (2): 157-170. 1985.
  •  19
    Seventeenth-Century Scholastic Treatments of Time
    Journal of the History of Ideas 42 (4): 587-606. 1981.
  •  558
    Berkeley, Suárez, and the Esse-Existere Distinction
    American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 74 (4): 621-636. 2000.
    For Berkeley, a thing's existence 'esse' is nothing more than its being perceived 'as that thing'. It makes no sense to ask (with Samuel Johnson) about the 'esse' of the mind or the specific act of perception, for that would be like asking what it means for existence to exist. Berkeley's "existere is percipi or percipere" (NB 429) thus carefully adopts the scholastic distinction between 'esse' and 'existere' ignored by Locke and others committed to a substantialist notion of mind. Following the …Read more
  •  42
    Wilhelm Dilthey (review)
    New Vico Studies 4 (n/a): 175-178. 1986.
  •  51
    Berkeley's 'Alciphron': English Text and Essays in Interpretation (review)
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 19 (3). 2011.
  •  74
    Metaphor in the Historiography of Philosophy
    Clio: A Journal of Literature, History, and the Philosophy of History 15 (2): 191-210. 1986.
  •  63
    Vico's historicism and the ontology of arguments
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 33 (3): 431-446. 1995.
    Vico's historicist claims (1) that different ages are intelligible only in their own terms and (2) that the certainty and authority of history depend on its narrative formulation seem at odds with his doctrines of ideal eternal history and divine providence. He resolves these issues, however, in his treatment of ideal eternal history by using the distinction between the certain and the true to show how rhetorical expression generates meaning in and as history. Specifically, by appealing to an on…Read more
  •  623
    Edwards' Occasionalism
    In Don Schweitzer (ed.), Jonathan Edwards as Contemporary, Peter Lang. pp. 1-14. 2010.
    Instead of focusing on the Malebranche-Edwards connection regarding occasionalism as if minds are distinct from the ideas they have, I focus on how finite minds are particular expressions of God's will that there be the distinctions by which ideas are identified and differentiated. This avoids problems, created in the accounts of Fiering, Lee, and especially Crisp, about the inherently idealist character of Edwards' occasionalism.
  •  8
    John Toland: His Methods, Manners, and Mind
    McGill-Queen's University Press. 1984.
    Drawing on a variety of published and unpublished material representing Toland's broad interests, Professor Daniel reveals a common theme emphasizing man's capacity for independent thought on basic philosophical, religious, and political issues. Roughly chronological, Daniel's treatment describes Toland's progressive refinement of this fundamental aspect of his thought. After examining, in his early works, the process whereby religion becomes mystified, Toland turned to biography, demonstrating …Read more
  •  36
    Ethical Theory and Journalistic Ethics
    International Journal of Applied Philosophy 1 (1): 19-25. 1982.
  •  4
    The Origins Of Certainty (review)
    Auslegung 7 296-98. 1980.