Saint Louis University
Department of Philosophy
PhD, 1977
College Station, Texas, United States of America
Areas of Specialization
17th/18th Century Philosophy
  •  47
    Descartes' Treatment of 'lumen naturale'
    Studia Leibnitiana 10 (1). 1978.
    Descartes’ “natural light” has been interpreted as a faculty of the mind, the sense-imagination-reason-under-standing composite, the principle of intellectual integrity and growth, or even God himself. In Meditations III and IV in particular, the meaning of lumen natural depends on recognizing how light and nature define one another and how “my nature” serves as the basis for pointing to what is beyond the domain of natural reason, including religious faith and natural belief (especially regardi…Read more
  •  645
    Berkeley's stoic notion of spiritual substance
    In Stephen Hartley Daniel (ed.), New Interpretations of Berkeley's Thought, Humanity Books. 2008.
    For Berkeley, minds are not Cartesian spiritual substances because they cannot be said to exist (even if only conceptually) abstracted from their activities. Similarly, Berkeley's notion of mind differs from Locke's in that, for Berkeley, minds are not abstract substrata in which ideas inhere. Instead, Berkeley redefines what it means for the mind to be a substance in a way consistent with the Stoic logic of 17th century Ramists on which Leibniz and Jonathan Edwards draw. This view of mind, I co…Read more
  •  54
    Reexamining Berkeley's Philosophy (edited book)
    University of Toronto Press. 2007.
    This collection confronts the question: how can we know anything about the world if all we know are our ideas?
  •  33
    New interpretations of Berkeley's thought (edited book)
    Humanity Books. 2008.
    In this set of previously unpublished essays, noted scholars from North America and Europe describe how the Irish philosopher George Berkeley (1684-1753) continues to inspire debates about his views on knowledge, reality, God, freedom, mathematics, and religion. Here discussions about Berkeley's account of physical objects, minds, and God's role in human experience are resolved within explicitly ethical and theological contexts. This collection uses debates about Berkeley's immaterialism and the…Read more
  •  66
    Berkeley and Spinoza
    Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 135 (1): 123-134. 2010.
    There is a widespread assumption that Berkeley and Spinoza have little in common, even though early Jesuit critics in France often linked them. Later commentators have also recognized their similarities. My essay focuses on how Berkeley 's comments on the Arnauld-Malebranche debate regarding objective and formal reality and his treatment of god's creation of finite minds within the order of nature relate his theory of knowledge to his doctrine in a way similar to that of Spinoza. On estime souve…Read more
  •  25
    L'Anthropologie de saint Thomas, ed. N. A. Luyten (review)
    Modern Schoolman 53 (3): 319-319. 1976.
  •  1344
    How Berkeley Redefines Substance
    Berkeley Studies 24 40-50. 2013.
    In several essays I have argued that Berkeley maintains the same basic notion of spiritual substance throughout his life. Because that notion is not the traditional (Aristotelian, Cartesian, or Lockean) doctrine of substance, critics (e.g., John Roberts, Tom Stoneham, Talia Mae Bettcher, Margaret Atherton, Walter Ott, Marc Hight) claim that on my reading Berkeley either endorses a Humean notion of substance or has no recognizable theory of substance at all. In this essay I point out how my inter…Read more
  • Senior Editor’s Note
    Berkeley Studies 18 2. 2007.
  •  29
    Postmodernity, Poststructuralism, and the Historiography of Modern Philosophy
    International Philosophical Quarterly 35 (3): 255-267. 1995.
    Well-known for its criticism of totalizing accounts of reason and truth, postmodern thought also makes positive contributions to our understanding of the sensual, ideological, and linguistic contingencies that inform modernist representations of self, history, and the world. The positive side of postmodernity includes structuralism and poststructuralism, particularly as expressed by theorists concerned with practices of the body (Lacan, Foucault, Deleuze), commodity differences (Adorno, Althusse…Read more
  • Book reviews (review)
    with Michael Littleford, Gary Shapiro, and Paul Fairfield
    Man and World 26 (2): 219-235. 1993.
  •  16
    Myth and the Grammar of Discovery in Francis Bacon
    Philosophy and Rhetoric 15 (4). 1982.
  • An explanation of how to organize and teach a course in recent continental thought, including treatments of the major figures in critical theory, hermeneutics, structuralism, deconstruction, psychoanalytic feminism, poststructuralism, postcolonialism, and postmodernism. Reprint from *In the Socratic Tradition: Essays on Teaching Philosophy*, ed. Tziporah Kasachkoff (Lanham, Md: Rowman and Littlefield, 1998).
  •  1068
    The ramist context of Berkeley's philosophy
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 9 (3). 2001.
    Berkeley's doctrines about mind, the language of nature, substance, minima sensibilia, notions, abstract ideas, inference, and freedom appropriate principles developed by the 16th-century logician Peter Ramus and his 17th-century followers (e.g., Alexander Richardson, William Ames, John Milton). Even though Berkeley expresses himself in Cartesian or Lockean terms, he relies on a Ramist way of thinking that is not a form of mere rhetoric or pedagogy but a logic and ontology grounded in Stoicism. …Read more
  •  13
    Contemporary Continental Thought
    Prentice-Hall. 2004.
    A survey with readings in critical theory, hermeneutics, structuralism, deconstruction, psychoanalytic feminism, poststructuralism, postcolonialism, and postmodernism. Aimed at students and scholars interested in an overview of movements in continental philosophy in the past century.
  •  51
    Edwards, Berkeley, and Ramist Logic
    Idealistic Studies 31 (1): 55-72. 2001.
    I will suggest that we can begin to see why Edwards and Berkeley sound so much alike by considering how both think of minds or spiritual substances notas things modeled on material bodies but as the acts by which things are identified. Those acts cannot be described using the Aristotelian subject-predicatelogic on which the metaphysics of substance, properties, attributes, or modes is based because subjects, substances, etc. are themselves initially distinguishedthrough such acts. To think of mi…Read more
  •  37
    The Narrative Character of Myth and Philosophy in Vico
    International Studies in Philosophy 20 (1): 1-9. 1988.
  •  22
  •  905
    Berkeley's Christian neoplatonism, archetypes, and divine ideas
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 39 (2): 239-258. 2001.
    Berkeley's doctrine of archetypes explains how God perceives and can have the same ideas as finite minds. His appeal of Christian neo-Platonism opens up a way to understand how the relation of mind, ideas, and their union is modeled on the Cappadocian church fathers' account of the persons of the trinity. This way of understanding Berkeley indicates why he, in contrast to Descartes or Locke, thinks that mind (spiritual substance) and ideas (the object of mind) cannot exist or be thought of apart…Read more
  •  1
    Lawrence J. Hatab, Myth and Philosophy: A Contest of Truths (review)
    Philosophy in Review 11 (5): 324-326. 1991.
    Review of Lawrence Hatab's *Myth and Philosophy*
  •  2
    William James (review)
    New Vico Studies 6 181-182. 1988.
  •  299
    Les limites de la philosophie naturelle de Berkeley
    In Sébastien Charles (ed.), Science et épistémologie selon Berkeley, Presses De L’université Laval. pp. 163-70. 2004.
    (Original French text followed by English version.) For Berkeley, mathematical and scientific issues and concepts are always conditioned by epistemological, metaphysical, and theological considerations. For Berkeley to think of any thing--whether it be a geometrical figure or a visible or tangible object--is to think of it in terms of how its limits make it intelligible. Especially in De Motu, he highlights the ways in which limit concepts (e.g., cause) mark the boundaries of science, metaphysic…Read more
  •  24
    William James (review)
    New Vico Studies 6 (n/a): 181-182. 1988.