•  793
    In the third chapter of his book Psychosemantics , Jerry A. Fodor argues that the truth of meaning holism (the thesis that the content of a psychological state is determined by the totality of that state's epistemic liaisons) would be fatal for intentionalistic psychology. This is because holism suggests that no two people are ever in the same intentional state, and so a psychological theory that generalizes over such states will be composed of generalizations which fail to generalize. Fodor the…Read more
  •  376
    On the Nature and Existence of God (review)
    Faith and Philosophy 12 (3): 432-434. 1995.
  •  30
    Introduction and Remembrance
    Journal of Philosophical Research 41 (9999): 7-9. 2016.
  •  627
    Dissatisfaction Theodicy and Punishment
    Southwest Philosophy Review 21 (2): 187-190. 2005.
  •  90
    Bread or stone? (review)
    The Philosophers' Magazine 66 125-126. 2014.
  •  4674
    The prima/ultima facie justification distinction in epistemology
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 56 (3): 551-566. 1996.
  •  1169
    In this paper I argue for a version of the Total Evidence view according to which the rational response to disagreement depends upon one's total evidence. I argue that perceptual evidence of a certain kind is significantly weightier than many other types of evidence, including testimonial. Furthermore, what is generally called "The Uniqueness Thesis" is actually a conflation of two distinct principles that I dub "Evidential Uniqueness" and "Rationality Uniqueness." The former principle is likely…Read more
  •  978
    God, Supernatural Kinds, and the Incarnation
    Religious Studies 27 (3): 353-370. 1991.
    Traditionally, the term ’God’ has been understood either as a proper name or as a description. However, according to a new view, the term God’ in a sentence like "Jesus Christ is God" functions as a kind term, much as the term ’tiger’ functions in the sentence "Tigger is a tiger." In this paper I examine the claim that divinity can be construed as a ’supernatural’ kind, developing the outlines of an account of the semantics of God’ along these lines, and suggest that it might solve an important …Read more
  •  2182
    Defending Divine Freedom
    In L. Kvanvig Jonathan (ed.), Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion, Oxford University Press. pp. 168-95. 2013.
  •  105
    Warrant (review)
    Review of Metaphysics 48 (4): 925-926. 1995.
  •  911
    The Incarnation and the Trinity
    In Michael J. Murray (ed.), Reason for the Hope Within, Wm. B. Eerdmans. 1999.
  •  1156
    The Incarnation
    In Chad Meister & Paul Copan (eds.), The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Religion, Routledge Press. 2007.
  •  2098
    Timothy O’Connor’s book Theism and Ultimate Explanation offers a defense of a new version of the cosmological argument. In his discussion, O’Connor argues against the coherence of a brute fact “explanation” of the universe and for the claim that the God of theism cannot be logically contingent. In this paper, I take issue with both of these arguments. Regarding the former, I claim that contrary to what O’Connor asserts, we have no good reason to prefer an account according to which the universe …Read more
  •  778
    Incarnation and Timeless
    Faith and Philosophy 7 (2): 149-164. 1990.
  •  20
    Common Core/Diversity Dilemma, Agatheism and the Epistemology of Religious Belief
    European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 8 (4): 213--226. 2016.
    The essay “The Common-Core/Diversity Dilemma: Revisions of Humean Thought, New Empirical Research, and the Limits of Rational Religious Belief‘ is a bold argument for the irrationality of “first-order‘ religious belief. However, unlike those associated with “New Atheism,‘ the paper’s authors Branden Thornhill-Miller and Peter Millican claim both that there are prospects for rational “second-order‘ religious belief and that religious belief and practice can play a positive role in human life. In …Read more
  •  19
    The Prima/Ultima Facie Justification Distinction in Epistemology
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 56 (3): 551-566. 1996.
  •  643
    Review of Paul K. Moser, The Evidence for God: Religious Knowledge Reexamined (review)
    Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2011 (1). 2011.
  •  87
    God, Supernatural Kinds, and the Incarnation: THOMAS D. SENOR
    Religious Studies 27 (3): 353-370. 1991.
    Thinking about God often leads to thinking about ‘God’. And it has never been completely clear how best to understand this little English word. Traditionally, ‘God’ has been taken to be either a description or a name. However, a third option has recently captured the attention of philosophical theologians. It is claimed that just as one should think of, say, ‘humanity’ as a kind term, so one should think of ‘God’, or perhaps ‘divinity’, as a kind term. But given the tight link between semantics …Read more
  •  844
    Drawing on Many Traditions: An Ecumenical Kenotic Christology
    In Anna Marmodoro & Jonathan Hill (eds.), The Metaphysics of the Incarnation, Oxford University Press. 2011.
  •  138
    Body and soul
    The Philosophers' Magazine 57 (57): 113-114. 2012.
  •  143
    The Knowledge-As-Perception Account of Knowledge
    Journal of Philosophical Research 41 (9999): 91-109. 2016.
    William Alston once argued that justification is not necessary for knowledge. He was convinced of this because he thought that, in cases of clear perception, one could come to know that P even if one’s justification for believing P was defeated. The idea is that the epistemic strength of clear perception is sufficient to provide knowledge even where justification is lacking; perceiving (and believing) that P is sufficient for knowing that P. In this paper, I explore a claim about knowledge that …Read more