•  18
    The Oxford Handbook of Berkeley (edited book)
    Oxford University Press. 2021.
    The Oxford Handbook of Berkeley is a compendious examination of a vast array of topics in the philosophy of George Berkeley, Anglican Bishop of Cloyne, the famous idealist and most illustrious Irish philosopher. Berkeley is best known for his denial of the existence of material substance and his insistence that the only things that exist in the universe are minds and their ideas; however, Berkeley was a polymath who contributed to a variety of different disciplines, not well distinguished from p…Read more
  •  61
    Hume's distinction between impressions and ideas
    European Journal of Philosophy 26 (4): 1222-1237. 2018.
    An important part of Hume's philosophy is grounded in a fundamental distinction between two kinds of perceptions: impressions and ideas. Existing views of the distinction are that the former are livelier than the latter, that the former are causally prior to the latter, that the latter are copies of the former, that the former but not the latter are perceptions of an objective realm, and that the former are feelings whereas the latter are thoughts. I argue that all of these views of the distinct…Read more
  •  22
    : Doing and Allowing Harm (review)
    Ethics 126 (3): 862-866. 2016.
  •  39
    Brief for an Inclusive Anti‐Canon
    Metaphilosophy 49 (1-2): 167-181. 2018.
    This article describes and defends an inclusive anti-canonical approach to the study of the history of philosophy. Its proposal, based on an analysis of the nature of the history of philosophy and the value of engaging in the practice, is this: The history of philosophy is the history of rationally justified, systematic answers to philosophical questions; studying this subject is both intrinsically and instrumentally valuable; these benefits do not derive from the imposition of a canon—indeed, t…Read more
  •  118
    Is Shepherd's pen mightier than Berkeley's word?
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 26 (2): 317-330. 2018.
    In 1827, Lady Mary Shepherd published Essays on the Perception of an External Universe, which offers both an argument for the existence of a world of external bodies existing outside our minds and a criticism of Berkeley's argument for idealism in A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge. In this paper, I evaluate Margaret Atherton's criticisms of Shepherd's case against Berkeley, and provide reasons for thinking that, although Shepherd's particular criticisms of Berkeley do not s…Read more
  •  122
    Is Locke’s Theory of Knowledge Inconsistent?
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 77 (1): 83-104. 2008.
    No Abstract
  •  114
    There is a mystery at the heart of Plato's Parmenides. In the first part, Parmenides criticizes what is widely regarded as Plato's mature theory of Forms, and in the second, he promises to explain how the Forms can be saved from these criticisms. Ever since the dialogue was written, scholars have struggled to determine how the two parts of the work fit together. Did Plato mean us to abandon, keep or modify the theory of Forms, on the strength of Parmenides' criticisms? Samuel Rickless offers som…Read more
  •  2
    Locke
    Wiley-Blackwell. 2014.
    In a focused assessment of one of the founding members of the liberal tradition in philosophy and a self-proclaimed “Under-Labourer” working to support the scientific revolution of the seventeenth century, the author maps the full range of John Locke’s highly influential ideas, which even today remain at the heart of debates about the nature of reality and our knowledge of it, as well as our moral and political rights and duties. Comprehensive introduction to the full range of Locke’s ideas, pro…Read more
  • Sinn Without Guilt: A Theory of Content for Singular Terms
    Dissertation, University of California, Los Angeles. 1996.
    Gottlob Frege and Bertrand Russell once argued over whether Mont Blanc is a constituent of the proposition that Mont Blanc is more than four thousand meters high. Russell thought so, but Frege disagreed. The debate has been with us ever since. ;Let us say that the content of a linguistic expression E is the entity contributed by E to the proposition expressed by a sentence of which E is a part. Russell's point, more generally, was that the content of a proper name, indexical or demonstrative is …Read more
  •  23
  •  20
    Qualities
    In Daniel Kaufman (ed.), The Routledge Companion to Seventeenth Century Philosophy, Routledge. pp. 60-86. 2014.
    One of the more interesting philosophical debates in the seventeenth century concerned the nature and explanation of qualities. In order to understand these debates, it is important to place them in their proper historical-philosophical context. This book chapter starts with theoretical background in the work of Aristotle and the atomists, and then moves on to survey various theories of motion and rest, light, color, and sound, as well as the distinction between primary and secondary qualities,…Read more
  •  132
    The Relation Between Anti-Abstractionism and Idealism in Berkeley's Metaphysics
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 20 (4): 723-740. 2012.
    George Berkeley maintains both anti-abstractionism (that abstract ideas are impossible) and idealism (that physical objects and their qualities are mind-dependent). Some scholars (including Atherton, Bolton, and Pappas) have argued, in different ways, that Berkeley uses anti-abstractionism as a premise in a simple argument for idealism. In this paper, I argue that the relation between anti-abstractionism and idealism in Berkeley's metaphysics is more complex than these scholars acknowledge. Berk…Read more
  •  139
    The Contrast‐Insensitivity of Knowledge Ascriptions
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 88 (3): 533-555. 2012.
  •  73
    Hume's Theory of Pity and Malice
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 21 (2): 324-344. 2013.
    (2013). Hume's Theory of Pity and Malice. British Journal for the History of Philosophy: Vol. 21, No. 2, pp. 324-344. doi: 10.1080/09608788.2012.692664
  •  140
    Why and How to Fill an Unfilled Proposition
    Theoria 78 (1): 6-25. 2011.
    There are two major semantic theories of proper names: Semantic Descriptivism and Direct Reference. According to Semantic Descriptivism, the semantic content of a proper name N for a speaker S is identical to the semantic content of a definite description “the F” that the speaker associates with the name. According to Direct Reference, the semantic content of a proper name is identical to its referent. Semantic Descriptivism suffers from a number of drawbacks first pointed out by Donnellan (1970…Read more
  •  35
    Plato, Metaphysics and the Forms (review)
    Ancient Philosophy 30 (2): 428-432. 2010.
  •  20
    A Synthetic Approach to Legal Adjudication
    San Diego Law Review 42 519-532. 2005.
    When faced with a dispute concerning how a given legal provision (whether constitutional or statutory) applies to a particular set of facts, how should a judge proceed? It is commonplace to say that, in the first instance, she should look to the meanings of the words that constitute the provision itself. If she is lucky, then the relevant meanings are clear; and if the facts are not in dispute, then the resolution is obvious. Unfortunately.
  •  146
  •  19
    Commentary: Miranda, Dickerson, and the problem of actual innocence
    Criminal Justice Ethics 19 (2): 53-55. 2000.
    No abstract
  •  73
    Marc A. Hight has given us a well-researched, well-written, analytically rigorous and thoughtprovoking book about the development of idea ontology in the seventeenth and early eighteenth centuries. The book covers a great deal of material, some in significant depth, some not. The figures discussed include Descartes, Malebranche, Arnauld, Locke, Leibniz, Berkeley, and Hume. Some might think it a tall order for anyone to grapple with the central works of these figures on a subject as fundamental a…Read more
  •  57
    The right to privacy unveiled
    San Diego Law Review 44 (1): 773-799. 2007.
    The vast majority of philosophers and legal theorists who have thought about the issue agree that there is such a thing as a moral right to privacy. However, there is little or no theoretical consensus about the nature of this right. According to reductionists, the right to privacy amounts to nothing more than a cluster of property rights and rights over the person, and therefore plays no autonomous explanatory role in moral theory (Thomson 1975, Davis 1959). Among non-reductionists, there are a…Read more
  •  65
    There are two major semantic theories of proper names: Semantic Descriptivism and Direct Reference. According to Semantic Descriptivism, the semantic content of a proper name N for a speaker S is identical to the semantic content of a definite description “the F” that the speaker associates with the name. According to Direct Reference, the semantic content of a proper name is identical to its referent. As is well known, Semantic Descriptivism suffers from a number of drawbacks first pointed out …Read more
  •  171
    The Moral Status of Enabling Harm
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 92 (1): 66-86. 2011.
    According to the Doctrine of Doing and Allowing, it is more difficult to justify doing harm than it is to justify allowing harm. Enabling harm consists in withdrawing an obstacle that would, if left in place, prevent a pre-existing causal sequence from leading to foreseen harm. There has been a lively debate concerning the moral status of enabling harm. According to some (e.g. McMahan, Vihvelin and Tomkow), many cases of enabling harm are morally indistinguishable from doing harm. Others (e.g. F…Read more
  •  112
    In the 17th century, there was a lively debate in the intellectual circles with which Locke was familiar, revolving around the question whether the human mind is furnished with innate ideas. Although a few scholars declared that there is no good reason to believe, and good reason not to believe, in the existence of innate ideas, the vast majority took for granted that God, in his infinite goodness and wisdom, has inscribed in human minds innate principles that constitute the foundation of knowle…Read more
  •  61
    Plato's parmenides
    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2008.
    The Parmenides is, quite possibly, the most enigmatic of Plato's dialogues. The dialogue recounts an almost certainly fictitious conversation between a venerable Parmenides (the Eleatic Monist) and a youthful Socrates, followed by a dizzying array of interconnected arguments presented by Parmenides to a young and compliant interlocutor named “Aristotle” (not the philosopher, but rather a man who became one of the Thirty Tyrants after Athens' surrender to Sparta at the conclusion of the Peloponne…Read more
  •  212
    The cartesian fallacy fallacy
    Noûs 39 (2): 309-336. 2005.
    In this paper, I provide what I believe to be Descartes's own solution to the problem of the Cartesian Circle. As I argue, Descartes thinks he can have certain knowledge of the premises of the Third Meditation proof of God's existence and veracity (i.e., the 3M-Proof) without presupposing God's existence. The key, as Broughton (1984) once argued, is that the premises of the 3M-Proof are knowable by the natural light. The major objection to this "natural light" gambit is that Descartes identifies…Read more
  •  169
    Socrates' moral intellectualism
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 79 (4): 355-367. 1998.
    In the Protagoras, Socrates appears to affirm and defend a paradoxical doctrine: the unity of virtue. Plato scholars do not agree on how the doctrine should be understood. Some, following Vlastos (1972), take Socrates to hold that the virtues are biconditionally related, i.e. that anyone who has one of the virtues has them all. Others, following Penner (1973), take Socrates’ position to be that the names of the virtues all refer to the same thing, namely virtue. In this paper, I argue that both …Read more