•  73
    The Natural Shiftiness of Natural Kinds
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 14 (4). 1984.
    The Philosophical search for Natural Kinds is motivated by the hope of finding ontological categories that are independent of our interests. Other requirements, of varying importance, are commonly made of kinds that claim to be natural. But no such categories are to be found. Virtually any kind can be termed 'natural' relative to some set of interests and epistemic priorities. Science determines those priorities at any particular stage of its progress, and what kinds are most 'natural' in that s…Read more
  • Die Rationalität der Emotionen
    In Sabine A. Döring (ed.), Philosophie der Gefühle, Suhrkamp. 2009.
  •  40
    Arts and Minds (review)
    Review of Metaphysics 60 (4): 860-861. 2007.
  •  26
    Les émotions contemplatives et l’objectivité des valeurs
    Philosophiques 45 (2): 499-505. 2018.
    Ronald de Sousa
  •  33
    "Emotion" by William Lyons (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 45 (1): 142-149. 1984.
  •  17
    L'erotisme
    In Julien A. Deonna & Emma Tieffenbach (eds.), Petit Traité des Valeurs, Edition D’ithaque. pp. 132-139. 2018.
  •  6
    Emotional Gestalten
    Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 19 (1): 13-15. 2012.
  •  4
    The Structure of Love.Alan Soble
    Ethics 101 (4): 867-868. 1991.
  •  22
    Types and Ontology
    with Fred Sommers and John O. Nelson
    Journal of Symbolic Logic 32 (3): 406-408. 1967.
  •  39
    Emotions, Education and Time
    Metaphilosophy 21 (4): 434-446. 1990.
  • Brian Easlea, Science and Sexual Oppression (review)
    Philosophy in Review 2 214-217. 1982.
  • Modelos conexionistas: consecuencias para la ciencia cognitiva
    Análisis Filosófico 9 (2): 183. 1989.
  •  46
    Kripke on Naming and Necessity
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 3 (3): 447-464. 1974.
    Some wag reported the following story: Scholars have recently established that the Iliad and the Odyssey were not, after all, written by Homer. They were actually written by another author, of the same name.The majority of current theories of naming and reference, including ones as divergent in other respects as those of Russell and Searle, would rule this story impossible. They would do so on roughly these grounds: the sense and reference of the name ‘Homer’ is determined, given the absence of …Read more
  •  12
    What Can’t We Do with Economics?
    Journal of Philosophical Research 22 197-209. 1997.
    Ainslie’s Picoeconomics presents an ingenious theory, based on a remarkably simple basic law about the rate of discounting the value of future prospects, which explains a vast number of psychological phenomena. Hyperbolic discount rates result in changes in the ranking of interests as they get closer in time. Thus quasi-homuncular “interests” situated at different times compete within the person. In this paper I first defend the generality of scope of Ainslie’s model, which ranges over several p…Read more
  •  168
  •  135
    The rationality of emotions
    Dialogue 18 (1): 41-63. 1979.
    Ira Brevis furor, said the Latins: anger is a brief bout of madness. There is a long tradition that views all emotions as threats to rationality. The crime passionnel belongs to that tradition: in law it is a kind of “brief-insanity defence.” We still say that “passion blinds us;” and in common parlance to be philosophical about life's trials is to be decently unemotional about them. Indeed many philosophers have espoused this view, demanding that Reason conquer Passion. Others — from Hume to th…Read more
  •  48
    Nothing seems to follow strictly from 'X believes that p'. But if we reinterpret it to mean: 'X can consistently be described as consistently believing p'--which roughly renders, I think, Hintikka's notion of "defensibility"--we can get on with the subject, freed from the inhibitions of descriptive adequacy. But defensibility is neither necessary nor sufficient for truth: it tells us little, therefore, about the concept of belief on which it is based. It cannot, in particular, specify necessary …Read more
  •  46
    Self-Deceptive Emotions
    Journal of Philosophy 75 (11). 1978.
  •  21
    Teleology and the Great Shift
    Journal of Philosophy 81 (11). 1984.
  •  45
    Kinds of kinds: Individuality and biological species
    International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 3 (2). 1989.
  •  47
    The sociology of sociobiology
    International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 4 (3). 1990.
    Abstract This paper turns the tables on the criticisms of sociobiology that stem from a sociological perspective; many of those criticisms lack cogency and coherence in such measure as to demand, in their turn, a psycho?sociological explanation rather than a rational justification. This thesis, after a brief exposition of the main ideas of sociobiology, is argued in terms of four of the most prominent complaints made against it. Far from embodying tired prejudices about the psychological and soc…Read more
  •  49
    Fringe consciousness and the multifariousness of emotions
    PSYCHE: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Research On Consciousness 8. 2002.
    Mangan draws his inspiration from James's account of fringe consciousness, but differs from James in focusing on something non-sensory, necessarily fuzzy, though not necessarily fleeting. A long tradition in philosophy has deemed non-sensory elements of consciousness to be indispensable to thought. But those, chiefly conceptual, forms of non-sensory fringe are not Mangan's focus. What then is Mangan talking about? This commentary envisages a number of possible answers, and tentatively concludes …Read more
  •  18
    Does the eye know calculus? The threshold of representation in classical and connectionist models
    International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 5 (2). 1991.
    Abstract The notion of representation lies at the crossroads of questions about the nature of belief and knowledge, meaning, and intentionality. But there is some hope that it might be simpler than all those. If we could understand it clearly, it might then help to explicate those more difficult notions. In this paper, my central aim is to find a principled criterion, along lines that make biological sense, for deciding just when it becomes theoretically plausible to ascribe to some process or s…Read more
  •  124
    Review of Jesse Prinz, The Emotional Construction of Morals (review)
    Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2008 (6). 2008.
  •  54
    Prcis of “why think?” Evolution and the rational mind
    American Journal of Bioethics 8 (5). 2008.
    This Article does not have an abstract