•  46
    Pv~P: Cambridge Journal of Undergraduate Philosophy, Issue 1, 1982.
  •  119
    Biohumanities: Rethinking the relationship between biosciences, philosophy and history of science, and society
    with Karola Stotz and Paul E. Griffiths
    Quarterly Review of Biology 83 (1): 37--45. 2007.
    We argue that philosophical and historical research can constitute a ‘Biohumanities’ which deepens our understanding of biology itself; engages in constructive 'science criticism'; helps formulate new 'visions of biology'; and facilitates 'critical science communication'. We illustrate these ideas with two recent 'experimental philosophy' studies of the concept of the gene and of the concept of innateness conducted by ourselves and collaborators.
  •  200
    Gut reactions: A perceptual theory of emotion (review)
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 59 (3): 559-567. 2008.
  •  28
    Cycles of Contingency: Developmental Systems and Evolution (edited book)
    with Susan Oyama and Russell D. Gray
    MIT Press. 2001.
    The nature/nurture debate is not dead. Dichotomous views of development still underlie many fundamental debates in the biological and social sciences. Developmental systems theory offers a new conceptual framework with which to resolve such debates. DST views ontogeny as contingent cycles of interaction among a varied set of developmental resources, no one of which controls the process. These factors include DNA, cellular and organismic structure, and social and ecological interactions. DST has …Read more
  •  111
    Molecular and Developmental Biology
    In Peter Machamer & Michael Silberstein (eds.), The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Science, Blackwell Publishers. pp. 252-271. 2002.
    Philosophical discussion of molecular and developmental biology began in the late 1960s with the use of genetics as a test case for models of theory reduction. With this exception, the theory of natural selection remained the main focus of philosophy of biology until the late 1970s. It was controversies in evolutionary theory over punctuated equilibrium and adaptationism that first led philosophers to examine the concept of developmental constraint. Developmental biology also gained in prominenc…Read more
  •  21
    A Sober View of Life (review)
    Biology and Philosophy 12 (3): 427-431. 1997.
  •  381
    Functional analysis and proper functions
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 44 (3): 409-422. 1993.
    The etiological approach to ‘proper functions’ in biology can be strengthened by relating it to Robert Cummins' general treatment of function ascription. The proper functions of a biological trait are the functions it is assigned in a Cummins-style functional explanation of the fitness of ancestors. These functions figure in selective explanations of the trait. It is also argued that some recent etiological theories include inaccurate accounts of selective explanation in biology. Finally, a gene…Read more
  • The Baldwin effect and Genetic assimilation: Contrasting explanatory foci and Gene concepts in two approaches to an evolutionary process
    In Peter Carruthers, Stephen Laurence & Stephen P. Stich (eds.), The Innate Mind: Culture and Cognition, Oxford University Press Usa. pp. 91-101. 2006.
    David Papineau (2003; 2005) has discussed the relationship between social learning and the family of postulated evolutionary processes that includes ‘organic selection’, ‘coincident selection’, ‘autonomisation’, ‘the Baldwin effect’ and ‘genetic assimilation’. In all these processes a trait which initially develops in the members of a population as a result of some interaction with the environment comes to develop without that interaction in their descendants. It is uncontroversial that the deve…Read more
  •  24
    Emotion and the problem of psychological categories
    In Alfred W. Kazniak (ed.), Emotions, Qualia and Consciousness, World Scientific. pp. 28--41. 2001.
    Emotion theory is beset by category disputes. Examining the nature and function of scientific classification can make some of these more tractable. The aim of classification is to group particulars into <<natural>> classes - classes whose members share a rich cluster of properties in addition to those used to place them in the class. Classification is inextricably linked to theories of the causal processes that explain why certain particulars resemble one another and so are usefully regarded as …Read more
  •  31
    Replicators and vehicles? Or developmental systems?
    with R. D. Gray
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4): 623-624. 1994.
  • Scientists’ Concepts of Innateness: Evolution or Attraction?
    with E. Machery, S. Linquist, and K. Stotz
    In Richard Samuels & Daniel A. Wilkenfeld (eds.), Advances in Experimental Philosophy of Science, Bloomsbury. pp. 172-201. 2019.
  •  103
    David Hull’s Natural Philosophy of Science
    Biology and Philosophy 15 (3): 301-310. 2000.
    Throughout his career David Hull has sought to bring the philosophy of science into closer contact with science and especially with biological science (Hull 1969, 1997b). This effort has taken many forms. Sometimes it has meant ‘either explaining basic biology to philosophers or explaining basic philosophy to biologists’ (Hull 1996, p. 77). The first of these tasks, simple as it sounds, has been responsible for revolutionary changes. It is well known that traditional philosophy of science, modele…Read more
  •  53
    Lost: One Gene Concept. Reward to Finder (review)
    Biology and Philosophy 17 (2): 271-283. 2002.
  •  58
    Liberals Ate My Genes?
    with Kenneth F. Schaffner, Ullica Segerstrale, and Steven Pinker
    Metascience 13 (1): 28-51. 2004.