•  192
    The basis of reference
    Erkenntnis 13 (1): 171--206. 1978.
  •  2575
    Meaning and Formal Semantics in Generative Grammar
    Erkenntnis 80 (1): 61-87. 2015.
    A generative grammar for a language L generates one or more syntactic structures for each sentence of L and interprets those structures both phonologically and semantically. A widely accepted assumption in generative linguistics dating from the mid-60s, the Generative Grammar Hypothesis , is that the ability of a speaker to understand sentences of her language requires her to have tacit knowledge of a generative grammar of it, and the task of linguistic semantics in those early days was taken to…Read more
  •  243
    Russell's theory of definite descriptions
    Mind 114 (456): 1135-1183. 2005.
    The proper statement and assessment of Russell's theory depends on one's semantic presuppositions. A semantic framework is provided, and Russell's theory formulated in terms of it. Referential uses of descriptions raise familiar problems for the theory, to which there are, at the most general level of abstraction, two possible Russellian responses. Both are considered, and both found wanting. The paper ends with a brief consideration of what the correct positive theory of definite descriptions m…Read more
  •  21
  •  1
    Functionalism and belief
    In Myles Brand & Robert M. Harnish (eds.), The Representation of Knowledge and Belief, University of Arizona Press. 1986.
  •  4
    Replies
    Philosophical Issues 10 (1): 321-343. 2000.
  •  9
    What Do Belief Ascrebers Really Mean? A Reply to Stephen Schiffer
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 77 (4): 404-423. 2017.
    Stephen Schiffer has recently claimed that the currently popular “hidden‐indexical” theory of belief reports is an implausible theory of such reports. His central argument for this claim is based on what he refers to as the “meaning‐intention” problem. In this paper, I claim that the meaning‐intention problem is powerless against the hidden‐indexical theory of belief reports. I further contend that the theory is in fact a plausible theory of such reports.
  •  3
    Critical notice (review)
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 7 (3): 637-650. 1977.
  •  4
    The Relational Theory of Belief [a Reply to Mark Richard]
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 71 (3): 240-245. 1990.
  •  274
    Meaning In Speech and In Thought
    Philosophical Quarterly 63 (250): 141-159. 2013.
    If we think in a lingua mentis, questions about relations between linguistic meaning and propositional-attitude content become questions about relations between meaning in a public language (p-meaning) and meaning in a language of thought (t-meaning). Whether or not the neo-Gricean is correct that p-meaning can be defined in terms of t-meaning and then t-meaning defined in terms of the causal-functional roles of mentalese expressions, it's apt to seem obvious that separate accounts are needed of…Read more
  •  64
    A normative theory of meaning (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65 (1). 2002.
    One has some idea of what to expect from the theory of meaning offered in The Grammar of Meaning even before opening the book, since Bob Brandom, who should know, says on the book’s jacket that, according to the authors