•  192
    The basis of reference
    Erkenntnis 13 (1): 171--206. 1978.
  •  2569
    Meaning and Formal Semantics in Generative Grammar
    Erkenntnis 80 (1): 61-87. 2015.
    A generative grammar for a language L generates one or more syntactic structures for each sentence of L and interprets those structures both phonologically and semantically. A widely accepted assumption in generative linguistics dating from the mid-60s, the Generative Grammar Hypothesis , is that the ability of a speaker to understand sentences of her language requires her to have tacit knowledge of a generative grammar of it, and the task of linguistic semantics in those early days was taken to…Read more
  •  584
    Meaning
    Clarendon Press. 1972.
    What is it for marks or sounds to have meaning, and what is it for someone to mean something in producing them? Answering these and related questions, Schiffer explores communication, speech acts, convention, and the meaning of linguistic items in this reissue of a seminal work on the foundations of meaning. A new introduction takes account of recent developments and places his theory in a broader context.
  •  240
    Russell's theory of definite descriptions
    Mind 114 (456): 1135-1183. 2005.
    The proper statement and assessment of Russell's theory depends on one's semantic presuppositions. A semantic framework is provided, and Russell's theory formulated in terms of it. Referential uses of descriptions raise familiar problems for the theory, to which there are, at the most general level of abstraction, two possible Russellian responses. Both are considered, and both found wanting. The paper ends with a brief consideration of what the correct positive theory of definite descriptions m…Read more
  •  21
  •  1
    Functionalism and belief
    In Myles Brand & Robert M. Harnish (eds.), The Representation of Knowledge and Belief, University of Arizona Press. 1986.
  •  4
    Replies
    Philosophical Issues 10 (1): 321-343. 2000.
  •  9
    What Do Belief Ascrebers Really Mean? A Reply to Stephen Schiffer
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 77 (4): 404-423. 2017.
    Stephen Schiffer has recently claimed that the currently popular “hidden‐indexical” theory of belief reports is an implausible theory of such reports. His central argument for this claim is based on what he refers to as the “meaning‐intention” problem. In this paper, I claim that the meaning‐intention problem is powerless against the hidden‐indexical theory of belief reports. I further contend that the theory is in fact a plausible theory of such reports.
  •  3
    Critical notice (review)
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 7 (3): 637-650. 1977.
  •  4
    The Relational Theory of Belief [a Reply to Mark Richard]
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 71 (3): 240-245. 1990.
  •  64
    A normative theory of meaning (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65 (1). 2002.
    One has some idea of what to expect from the theory of meaning offered in The Grammar of Meaning even before opening the book, since Bob Brandom, who should know, says on the book’s jacket that, according to the authors
  •  274
    Meaning In Speech and In Thought
    Philosophical Quarterly 63 (250): 141-159. 2013.
    If we think in a lingua mentis, questions about relations between linguistic meaning and propositional-attitude content become questions about relations between meaning in a public language (p-meaning) and meaning in a language of thought (t-meaning). Whether or not the neo-Gricean is correct that p-meaning can be defined in terms of t-meaning and then t-meaning defined in terms of the causal-functional roles of mentalese expressions, it's apt to seem obvious that separate accounts are needed of…Read more
  •  30
    Symposium on Remnants of Meaning
    Mind and Language 3 (1): 1-63. 1988.
  •  149
    Interest-Relative Invariantism (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 75 (1). 2007.
    In his important book Knowledge and Practical Interests, Jason Stanley advances a proposal about knowledge and the semantics of knowledge ascriptions which he calls interest-relative invariantism. A theory of knowledge ascriptions of the form ‘A knows that S’ is invariantist
  •  90
    Kripkenstein meets the remnants of meaning
    Philosophical Studies 49 (March): 147-162. 1986.
  •  1
    Remnants of Meaning
    Studia Logica 49 (3): 427-428. 1990.
  •  81
    Intention-Based Semantics
    Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 23 (2): 119--156. 1982.
  •  228
    Although there is a vast literature on whether propositional attitudes are relations to propositions, a crucial question that ought to lie at the heart of this debate is not often enough seriously addressed. This is the question of the contribution propositions make to the ways in which we benefit from having our propositional-attitude concepts, if those concepts are concepts of relations to propositions. Unless propositions can be shown to confer a benefit that no non-propositions could provide…Read more
  •  18
    The Varieties of Reference by Gareth Evans (review)
    Journal of Philosophy 85 (1): 33-42. 1988.
  •  2
    Cognition and Representation (edited book)
    with Susan Steele
    Westview Press. 1988.
  •  7
    The Language-of-Thought Relation and Its Implications
    Philosophical Issues 5 155-175. 1994.
  •  91
    A Paradox of Desire
    American Philosophical Quarterly 13 (3). 1976.
  •  38
    Paradox and the A Priori
    In Tamar Szabó Gendler & John Hawthorne (eds.), Oxford Studies in Epistemology, Oxford University Press. pp. 1--273. 2005.
  •  386
    The epistemic theory of vagueness
    Philosophical Perspectives 13 481-503. 1999.
  •  86
    Meanings and concepts
    Lingua E Stile 33 (3): 399-411. 1998.