•  3
    III*—Intentionality and the Language of Thought
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 87 (1): 35-56. 1987.
    Stephen Schiffer; III*—Intentionality and the Language of Thought, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 87, Issue 1, 1 June 1987, Pages 35–56, https
  • Meaning
    Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 35 (3): 669-671. 1973.
  • The Things We Mean
    Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 66 (2): 395-395. 2003.
  •  1
    Remnants of Meaning
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 50 (2): 409-423. 1989.
  •  25
    Précis of The Things We Mean
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 73 (1): 208-210. 2006.
    In The Things We Mean I argue that there exist such things as the things we mean and believe, and that they are what I call pleonastic propositions. The first two chapters offer an initial motivation and articulation of the theory of pleonastic propositions, and of pleonastic entities generally. The remaining six chapters bring that theory to bear on issues in the theory of content: the existence and nature of meanings; knowledge of meaning; the meaning relation and compositional semantics; the …Read more
  • Meaning
    Philosophy 51 (195): 102-109. 1972.
  •  79
    Horwich on Meaning
    Philosophical Quarterly 50 (201): 527-536. 2000.
  • The Things We Mean
    Philosophical Quarterly 56 (223): 301-303. 2006.
  •  15
    Précis of The Things We Mean
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 73 (1): 208-210. 2007.
    In The Things We Mean I argue that there exist such things as the things we mean and believe, and that they are what I call pleonastic propositions. The first two chapters offer an initial motivation and articulation of the theory of pleonastic propositions, and of pleonastic entities generally. The remaining six chapters bring that theory to bear on issues in the theory of content: the existence and nature of meanings; knowledge of meaning; the meaning relation and compositional semantics; the …Read more
  •  10
    Facing Facts’ Consequences
    ProtoSociology 23 50-66. 2006.
  •  21
  •  1
    Functionalism and belief
    In Myles Brand & Robert M. Harnish (eds.), The Representation of Knowledge and Belief, University of Arizona Press. 1986.
  •  241
    Russell's theory of definite descriptions
    Mind 114 (456): 1135-1183. 2005.
    The proper statement and assessment of Russell's theory depends on one's semantic presuppositions. A semantic framework is provided, and Russell's theory formulated in terms of it. Referential uses of descriptions raise familiar problems for the theory, to which there are, at the most general level of abstraction, two possible Russellian responses. Both are considered, and both found wanting. The paper ends with a brief consideration of what the correct positive theory of definite descriptions m…Read more
  •  3
    Critical notice (review)
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 7 (3): 637-650. 1977.
  •  4
    Replies
    Philosophical Issues 10 (1): 321-343. 2000.
  •  9
    What Do Belief Ascrebers Really Mean? A Reply to Stephen Schiffer
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 77 (4): 404-423. 2017.
    Stephen Schiffer has recently claimed that the currently popular “hidden‐indexical” theory of belief reports is an implausible theory of such reports. His central argument for this claim is based on what he refers to as the “meaning‐intention” problem. In this paper, I claim that the meaning‐intention problem is powerless against the hidden‐indexical theory of belief reports. I further contend that the theory is in fact a plausible theory of such reports.
  •  4
    The Relational Theory of Belief [a Reply to Mark Richard]
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 71 (3): 240-245. 1990.
  •  274
    Meaning In Speech and In Thought
    Philosophical Quarterly 63 (250): 141-159. 2013.
    If we think in a lingua mentis, questions about relations between linguistic meaning and propositional-attitude content become questions about relations between meaning in a public language (p-meaning) and meaning in a language of thought (t-meaning). Whether or not the neo-Gricean is correct that p-meaning can be defined in terms of t-meaning and then t-meaning defined in terms of the causal-functional roles of mentalese expressions, it's apt to seem obvious that separate accounts are needed of…Read more
  •  64
    A normative theory of meaning (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65 (1). 2002.
    One has some idea of what to expect from the theory of meaning offered in The Grammar of Meaning even before opening the book, since Bob Brandom, who should know, says on the book’s jacket that, according to the authors
  •  149
    Interest-Relative Invariantism (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 75 (1). 2007.
    In his important book Knowledge and Practical Interests, Jason Stanley advances a proposal about knowledge and the semantics of knowledge ascriptions which he calls interest-relative invariantism. A theory of knowledge ascriptions of the form ‘A knows that S’ is invariantist
  •  90
    Kripkenstein meets the remnants of meaning
    Philosophical Studies 49 (March): 147-162. 1986.
  •  30
    Symposium on Remnants of Meaning
    Mind and Language 3 (1): 1-63. 1988.
  •  81
    Intention-Based Semantics
    Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 23 (2): 119--156. 1982.
  •  1
    Remnants of Meaning
    Studia Logica 49 (3): 427-428. 1990.
  •  2
    Cognition and Representation (edited book)
    with Susan Steele
    Westview Press. 1988.
  •  228
    Although there is a vast literature on whether propositional attitudes are relations to propositions, a crucial question that ought to lie at the heart of this debate is not often enough seriously addressed. This is the question of the contribution propositions make to the ways in which we benefit from having our propositional-attitude concepts, if those concepts are concepts of relations to propositions. Unless propositions can be shown to confer a benefit that no non-propositions could provide…Read more