•  48
    Intentionality and the language of thought
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 87 35-55. 1987.
    Stephen Schiffer; III*—Intentionality and the Language of Thought, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 87, Issue 1, 1 June 1987, Pages 35–56, https
  •  47
    A Normative Theory of Meaning
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65 (1): 186-192. 2002.
    One has some idea of what to expect from the theory of meaning offered in The Grammar of Meaning even before opening the book, since Bob Brandom, who should know, says on the book’s jacket that, according to the authors
  •  42
    Vagueness and Partial Belief
    Philosophical Issues 10 (1): 220-257. 2000.
  •  38
    Paradox and the A Priori
    In Tamar Szabó Gendler & John Hawthorne (eds.), Oxford Studies in Epistemology, Oxford University Press. pp. 1--273. 2005.
  •  37
    Reply to Ray
    Noûs 29 (3): 397-401. 1995.
  •  37
    Williamson on Our Ignorance in Borderline Cases
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 57 (4). 1997.
  •  35
    Reply to Yagisawa
    Philosophical Studies 76 (2-3). 1994.
  •  33
    Replies (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 73 (1). 2006.
    There are important differences among those philosophers who would call themselves nominalists and thus claim to disbelieve in the existence of numbers, properties, propositions, and their ilk. Some are non-concessive, and would deny that sentences such as following can be true
  •  32
    Stalnaker's problem of intentionality: On Robert Stalnaker's inquiry
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 67 (April): 87-97. 1986.
  •  30
    Symposium on Remnants of Meaning
    Mind and Language 3 (1): 1-63. 1988.
  •  29
    There are two things we must know in order to know what vagueness is. We must know what kinds of things can be vague. Evidently, predicate and sentence types can be vague, but what about tokens of those types? What about statements and other speech acts? What about abstract entities such as properties and propositions? And what about names and the boundaries of physical objects? Then, of course, for each kind of thing that can be vague, we must know in what vagueness for that kind consists. Need…Read more
  •  28
    Correspondence & Disquotation (review)
    International Studies in Philosophy 28 (4): 112-113. 1996.
  •  27
    The Varieties of Reference
    Journal of Philosophy 85 (1): 33-42. 1988.
  •  27
    On Saying and Being
    Analysis 25 (Suppl-3). 1965.
  •  26
    Replies (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 73 (1): 233-243. 2007.
    There are important differences among those philosophers who would call themselves nominalists and thus claim to disbelieve in the existence of numbers, properties, propositions, and their ilk. Some are non-concessive, and would deny that sentences such as following can be true
  •  24
    Précis of The Things We Mean
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 73 (1): 208-210. 2006.
    In The Things We Mean I argue that there exist such things as the things we mean and believe, and that they are what I call pleonastic propositions. The first two chapters offer an initial motivation and articulation of the theory of pleonastic propositions, and of pleonastic entities generally. The remaining six chapters bring that theory to bear on issues in the theory of content: the existence and nature of meanings; knowledge of meaning; the meaning relation and compositional semantics; the …Read more
  •  21
  •  20
    Overview of the Book
    Mind and Language 3 (1): 1-8. 1988.
  •  18
    The Varieties of Reference by Gareth Evans (review)
    Journal of Philosophy 85 (1): 33-42. 1988.
  •  18
    That-Clauses and the Semantics of Belief Reports
    Facta Philosophica 5 (2): 163-180. 2003.
  •  16
    Book review (review)
    Linguistics and Philosophy 19 (1): 91-102. 1996.
  •  15
    Intention and Convention in the Theory of Meaning
    In Bob Hale, Crispin Wright & Alexander Miller (eds.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Language, Wiley. 2017.
    This chapter focuses on a question: how does the intentionality of language 'derive' from the original intentionality of thought. Hardly any philosopher of language would deny that if something is an expression which has meaning in a population, then that is by virtue of facts about the linguistic behavior and psychological states of members of that population. The chapter starts with a reconstruction of Lewis's account of the relation in Convention because a problem that immediately arises for …Read more
  •  15
    Review: Horwich on Meaning (review)
    Philosophical Quarterly 50 (201). 2000.
  •  15
    Précis of The Things We Mean
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 73 (1): 208-210. 2007.
    In The Things We Mean I argue that there exist such things as the things we mean and believe, and that they are what I call pleonastic propositions. The first two chapters offer an initial motivation and articulation of the theory of pleonastic propositions, and of pleonastic entities generally. The remaining six chapters bring that theory to bear on issues in the theory of content: the existence and nature of meanings; knowledge of meaning; the meaning relation and compositional semantics; the …Read more
  •  14
    Reply to Comments
    Mind and Language 3 (1): 53-63. 1988.