Columbia University
Department of Philosophy
PhD, 1986
Stanford, California, United States of America
  •  25
    Russell and Analytic Philosophy
    with A. D. Irving and G. A. Wedeking
    Philosophical Quarterly 46 (184): 425. 1996.
  •  20
    Philosophy of Science and its Discontents
    Noûs 27 (2): 261-264. 1993.
  •  18
    Proper Names, Beliefs, and Definite Descriptions
    Dissertation, University of Massachusetts Amherst. 1984.
    This dissertation investigates issues raised by these two questions: what kinds of propositions are ordinarily expressed by uses of sentences that contain proper names; and what kinds of beliefs are ordinarily on the minds of speakers when they use sentences that contain proper names? It develops a new view about the connections between beliefs, linguistic behavior, and propositional content, one that explicitly denies that the kinds of propositions typically expressed by uses of such sentences …Read more
  •  14
    Those enlightened philosophers of physics acknowledging some manner of descent from Kant’s ‘Copernican Revolution’ have long found encouragement and inspiration in the writings of Roberto Torretti. In this tribute, I focus on his “perspective on Kant’s perspective on objectivity” (2008), a short but highly stimulating attempt to extract the essential core of the Kantian doctrine that ‘objects of knowledge’ are constituted, not given, or with Roberto’s inimitable pungency, that “objectivity is an…Read more
  •  14
    Contingency, a Prioricity and Acquaintance
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 53 (2): 323-343. 1993.
  •  9
    Hilbert on General Covariance and Causality
    In David E. Rowe, Tilman Sauer & Scott A. Walter (eds.), Beyond Einstein: Perspectives on Geometry, Gravitation, and Cosmology in the Twentieth Century, Springer New York. pp. 67-77. 2018.
    Einstein and Hilbert both struggled to reconcile general covariance and causality in their early work on general relativity. In Einstein’s case, this first led to his infamous “hole argument”, a stumbling block that persuaded him early on that generally covariant field equations for gravitation could never be found. After his breakthrough to general covariance in the fall of 1915, the resolution came in form of the “point-coincidence argument.” Hilbert from the beginning took a different view of…Read more
  •  9
    Recovering First Philosophy in Philosophy of Physics
    Philosophy Today 49 (Supplement): 13-22. 2005.
  •  8
    Book Reviews (review)
    with Doohwan Ahn, Nataša Bakić-Mirić, Giorgio Baruchello, Cristina M. Bettin, Martine Benjamin, Michael Bonura, Peter Burke, Camelia Mihaela Cmeciu, John M. Cox, Janina K. Darling, Donald J. Dietrich, Liviu Drugus, Daphna Erdinast-Vulcan, Steven L. Goldman, Boris Gubman, Grant Havers, Stefan Höjelid, Javier A. Ibáñez-Noé, Horst Jesse, Rachael Lorna Johnstone, Steven Joyce, Yves Laberge, David W. Lovell, Joseph Mali, Glenn W. Olsen, Bruce F. Pauley, Duncan Richter, Sheldon Rothblatt, Arthur B. Shostak, Stanley Shostak, Barnard Turner, Timothy Unwin, Frederick G. Whelan, and Warren C. Wood
    The European Legacy 13 (7): 877-916. 2008.
  •  7
    Otto Neurath (review)
    Philosophical Review 107 (2): 327-329. 1998.
    This collaborative work provides an intellectual portrait of a man known to most students of philosophy today only as a lesser founding member of the Vienna Circle. It makes a strong case for the intrinsic interest and continuing relevance of much of Neurath’s thought to contemporary science studies, considered broadly. Together with several other recent works on Neurath, it forces a substantial revision in any assessment of the Vienna Circle and its legacy. Finally, it describes, in some detail…Read more
  •  7
    Designation and Convention: A Chapter of Early Logical Empiricism
    PSA Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1990 (2): 149-157. 1990.
    We have yet to fully understand the mariner or the measure to which logical empiricism emerged as a conventionalist response to both traditional Kantian and empiricist epistemology and to the apparent triumphs of “conventionalist stratagems” (in Popper’s aspersive locution) in the foundations of science. By “conventionalism”, however, is here understood a broader sense than customary, an extrapolation of views on the foundations of geometry and physics (associated in the first instance with Poin…Read more
  •  6
    Einstein
    Routledge. 2017.
    Albert Einstein was the most influential physicist of the twentieth century. Less well-known is that fundamental philosophical problems, such as concept formation, the role of epistemology in developing and explaining the character of physical theories, and the debate between positivism and realism, played a central role in his thought as a whole. Thomas Ryckman shows that already at the beginning of his career, at a time when the twin pillars of classical physics, Newtonian mechanics and Maxwel…Read more
  • QBism : realism about what?
    In Philipp Berghofer & Harald A. Wiltsche (eds.), Phenomenology and Qbism: New Approaches to Quantum Mechanics, Routledge. 2023.