•  1257
    Water is and is not H 2 O
    with Kevin P. Tobia and George E. Newman
    Mind and Language 35 (2): 183-208. 2019.
    The Twin Earth thought experiment invites us to consider a liquid that has all of the superficial properties associated with water (clear, potable, etc.) but has entirely different deeper causal properties (composed of “XYZ” rather than of H2O). Although this thought experiment was originally introduced to illuminate questions in the theory of reference, it has also played a crucial role in empirically informed debates within the philosophy of psychology about people’s ordinary natural kind conc…Read more
  •  697
    Causal superseding
    with Jonathan F. Kominsky, Jonathan Phillips, Tobias Gerstenberg, and David Lagnado
    Cognition 137 (C): 196-209. 2015.
    When agents violate norms, they are typically judged to be more of a cause of resulting outcomes. In this paper, we suggest that norm violations also affect the causality attributed to other agents, a phenomenon we refer to as "causal superseding." We propose and test a counterfactual reasoning model of this phenomenon in four experiments. Experiments 1 and 2 provide an initial demonstration of the causal superseding effect and distinguish it from previously studied effects. Experiment 3 shows t…Read more
  •  11
    Guest Editorial
    Journal of the Indian Council of Philosophical Research 34 (3): 443-445. 2017.
  • Oxford Studies in Experimental Philosophy, Volume Two (edited book)
    with Tania Lombrozo and Shaun Nichols
    Oxford University Press. 2018.
  •  1049
    Consistent Belief in a Good True Self in Misanthropes and Three Interdependent Cultures
    with Julian De Freitas, Hagop Sarkissian, George E. Newman, Igor Grossmann, Felipe De Brigard, and Andres Luco
    Cognitive Science 42 (S1): 134-160. 2018.
    People sometimes explain behavior by appealing to an essentialist concept of the self, often referred to as the true self. Existing studies suggest that people tend to believe that the true self is morally virtuous; that is deep inside, every person is motivated to behave in morally good ways. Is this belief particular to individuals with optimistic beliefs or people from Western cultures, or does it reflect a widely held cognitive bias in how people understand the self? To address this question…Read more
  •  980
    The Influence of Social Interaction on Intuitions of Objectivity and Subjectivity
    with Fisher Matthew, Strickland Brent, and C. Keil Frank
    Cognitive Science 41 (4): 1119-1134. 2017.
    We present experimental evidence that people's modes of social interaction influence their construal of truth. Participants who engaged in cooperative interactions were less inclined to agree that there was an objective truth about that topic than were those who engaged in a competitive interaction. Follow-up experiments ruled out alternative explanations and indicated that the changes in objectivity are explained by argumentative mindsets: When people are in cooperative arguments, they see the …Read more
  •  8
    Dual Character Concepts
    with Sandeep Prasada
  •  3
    Intuitions in the test-tube
    The Philosophers' Magazine 28 37-39. 2004.
  •  2160
    Normality: Part Descriptive, part prescriptive
    with Adam Bear
    Cognition 167 (C): 25-37. 2017.
    People’s beliefs about normality play an important role in many aspects of cognition and life (e.g., causal cognition, linguistic semantics, cooperative behavior). But how do people determine what sorts of things are normal in the first place? Past research has studied both people’s representations of statistical norms (e.g., the average) and their representations of prescriptive norms (e.g., the ideal). Four studies suggest that people’s notion of normality incorporates both of these types of n…Read more
  •  590
    Differences in the Evaluation of Generic Statements About Human and Non‐Human Categories
    with Arber Tasimi, Susan Gelman, and Andrei Cimpian
    Cognitive Science 41 (7): 1934-1957. 2017.
    Generic statements express generalizations about categories. Current theories suggest that people should be especially inclined to accept generics that involve threatening information. However, previous tests of this claim have focused on generics about non-human categories, which raises the question of whether this effect applies as readily to human categories. In Experiment 1, adults were more likely to accept generics involving a threatening property for artifacts, but this negativity bias di…Read more
  •  192
    The essence of essentialism
    with George E. Newman
    Mind and Language 34 (5): 585-605. 2019.
    Over the past several decades, psychological essentialism has been an important topic of study, incorporating research from multiple areas of psychology, philosophy and linguistics. At its most basic level, essentialism is the tendency to represent certain concepts in terms of a deeper, unobservable property that is responsible for category membership. Originally, this concept was used to understand people’s reasoning about natural kind concepts, such as TIGER and WATER, but more recently, resea…Read more
  •  988
    Beliefs About the True Self Explain Asymmetries Based on Moral Judgment
    with George E. Newman and Julian De Freitas
    Cognitive Science 39 (1): 96-125. 2015.
    Past research has identified a number of asymmetries based on moral judgments. Beliefs about what a person values, whether a person is happy, whether a person has shown weakness of will, and whether a person deserves praise or blame seem to depend critically on whether participants themselves find the agent's behavior to be morally good or bad. To date, however, the origins of these asymmetries remain unknown. The present studies examine whether beliefs about an agent's “true self” explain these…Read more
  •  499
    Experimental philosophy
    Philosophy Compass 2 (1). 2006.
    Claims about people's intuitions have long played an important role in philosophical debates. The new field of experimental philosophy seeks to subject such claims to rigorous tests using the traditional methods of cognitive science – systematic experimentation and statistical analysis. Work in experimental philosophy thus far has investigated people's intuitions in philosophy of language, philosophy of mind, epistemology, and ethics. Although it is now generally agreed that experimental philoso…Read more
  •  299
    The good, the bad and the blameworthy: Understanding the role of evaluative reasoning in folk psychology
    with Gabriel S. Mendlow
    Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology 24 (2): 252-258. 2004.
    People ordinarily make sense of their own behavior and that of others by invoking concepts like belief, desire, and intention. Philosophers refer to this network of concepts and related principles as 'folk psychology.' The prevailing view of folk psychology among philosophers of mind and psychologists is that it is a proto-scientific theory whose function is to explain and predict behavior
  •  85
    Acting intentionally and acting for a reason
    Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology 27 (1): 119-122. 2007.
    In earlier work, I relied on a commonly-held view about the relationship between the concept of acting intentionally and the concept of performing a behavior in order to achieve a goal. Eric Wiland responds that it was actually a mistake to rely on this view and that the relationship between these concepts is far more complex than was previously thought. I now think that Wiland may be right to reject my earlier approach, and I therefore provide additional empirical support for his basic claim. 2…Read more
  •  433
    Philosophical implications of inflationary cosmology
    with Ken D. Olum and And Alexander Vilenkin
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 57 (1): 47-67. 2006.
    Recent developments in cosmology indicate that every history having a non-zero probability is realized in infinitely many distinct regions of spacetime. Thus, it appears that the universe contains infinitely many civilizations exactly like our own, as well as infinitely many civilizations that differ from our own in any way permitted by physical laws. We explore the implications of this conclusion for ethical theory and for the doomsday argument. In the infinite universe, we find that the doomsd…Read more
  •  1221
    Past work has demonstrated that people’s moral judgments can influence their judgments in a number of domains that might seem to involve straightforward matters of fact, including judgments about freedom, causation, the doing/allowing distinction, and intentional action. The present studies explore whether the effect of morality in these four domains can be explained by changes in the relevance of alternative possibilities. More precisely, we propose that moral judgment influences the degree to …Read more
  •  1384
    Normative Judgments and Individual Essence
    with Julian De Freitas, Kevin P. Tobia, and George E. Newman
    Cognitive Science 41 (S3): 382-402. 2017.
    A growing body of research has examined how people judge the persistence of identity over time—that is, how they decide that a particular individual is the same entity from one time to the next. While a great deal of progress has been made in understanding the types of features that people typically consider when making such judgments, to date, existing work has not explored how these judgments may be shaped by normative considerations. The present studies demonstrate that normative beliefs do a…Read more
  •  116
    What is experimental philosophy?
    The Philosophers' Magazine 28 37-39. 2004.
    Since the earliest days of analytic philosophy, it has been a common practice to appeal to intuitions about particular cases. Typically, the philosopher presents a hypothetical situation and then makes a claim of the form: ‘In this case, we would surely say....’ This claim about people’s intuitions then forms a part of an argument for some more general theory about the nature of our concepts or our use of language. One puzzling aspect of this practice is that it so rarely makes use of standard e…Read more
  •  3
  •  136
    The case for Nietzschean moral psychology
    In Brian Leiter & Neil Sinhababu (eds.), Nietzsche and morality, Oxford University Press. 2007.
    Contemporary moral psychology has been dominated by two broad traditions, one usually associated with Aristotle, the other with Kant. The broadly Aristotelian approach emphasizes the role of childhood upbringing in the development of good moral character, and the role of such character in ethical behavior. The broadly Kantian approach emphasizes the role of freely chosen conscious moral principles in ethical behavior. We review a growing body of experimental evidence that suggests that both of t…Read more
  •  166
    Ordinary ethical reasoning and the ideal of 'being yourself'
    Philosophical Psychology 18 (3). 2005.
    The psychological study of ethical reasoning tends to concentrate on a few specific issues, with the bulk of the research going to the study of people's attitudes toward moral rules or the welfare of others. But people's ethical reasoning is also shaped by a wide range of other concerns. Here I focus on the importance that people attach to the ideal of being yourself. It is shown that certain experimental results - results that seemed anomalous and inexplicable to researchers who focused on mora…Read more
  •  831
    Free Will and the Scientific Vision
    In Edouard Machery & Elizabeth O'Neill (eds.), Current Controversies in Experimental Philosophy, Routledge. 2014.
    A review of existing work in experimental philosophy on intuitions about free will. The paper argues that people ordinarily understand free human action, not as something that is caused by psychological states (beliefs, desires, etc.) but as something that completely transcends the normal causal order.
  •  570
    There has been a long-standing dispute in the philosophical literature about the conditions under which a behavior counts as 'intentional.' Much of the debate turns on questions about the use of certain words and phrases in ordinary language. The present paper investigates these questions empirically, using experimental techniques to investigate people's use of the relevant words and phrases. g.
  •  1666
    Contrastive Knowledge Surveyed
    Noûs 46 (4): 675-708. 2010.
    Suppose that Ann says, “Keith knows that the bank will be open tomorrow.” Her audience may well agree. Her knowledge ascription may seem true. But now suppose that Ben—in a different context—also says “Keith knows that the bank will be open tomorrow.” His audience may well disagree. His knowledge ascription may seem false. Indeed, a number of philosophers have claimed that people’s intuitions about knowledge ascriptions are context sensitive, in the sense that the very same knowledge ascription …Read more
  •  30
    Experimental philosophy
    The Philosophers' Magazine 50 72-73. 2007.
  •  140
    Theory of mind and moral cognition: Exploring the connections
    Trends in Cognitive Science 9 (8): 357-359. 2005.
    An extremely brief (3 page) review of recent work on the ways in which people's moral judgments can influence their use of folk-psychological concepts