•  20
    Reid and His French Disciples (review)
    International Studies in Philosophy 30 (2): 138-139. 1998.
  •  5
    "N. Grimaldi": L'expérience de la pensée dans la philosophie de Descartes (review)
    Revue de Théologie Et de Philosophie 112 (n/a): 211. 1980.
    A review of Nicolas Grimaldi’s L’expérience de la pensée dans la philosophie de Descartes (1978), a work proposing an interpretation of Descartes which disentangles the (“rhizomatic”) “experience of thought” in Descartes’ philosophy from the “order of reasons” of his system (cf. Martial Gueroult). In his intellectual development, Descartes successively explores three orders of thoughts: the order of truth, the order of utility, and the order of freedom.
  •  9
    Fernand Brunner, philosophe (1920-1991)
    Revue de Théologie Et de Philosophie 42 (n/a): 1. 1992.
    In commemoration of Ferdinand Brunner (1929-1991), a short biography of this important figure in Swiss and French intellectual life.
  •  31
    The Context of the Stewart–Prevost Correspondence
    with Claire Etchegaray, Knud Haakonssen, David Stauffer, and Paul Wood
    History of European Ideas 38 (1): 5-18. 2012.
    Summary The correspondence in this issue of History of European Ideas has not previously been published. It is the surviving part of the epistolary exchange between Dugald Stewart and the Genevan professor and man of letters Pierre Prevost (1751?1839) from the 1790s to the 1820s. To this are added several closely connected letters to and from their associates. This correspondence is striking evidence of the republic of letters continuing to flourish in the aftermath of the French Revolution, ill…Read more
  •  19
    Psychologie et épistémologie de la croyance selon Hume
    Dialectica 47 (2‐3): 255-267. 1993.
    RésuméDans son Traité, Hume a voulu, en un premier temps, dégager une conception purement psychologique et naturaliste de la croyance, et ainsi en exclure l'éaluation par une épistémologie normative. Dans un second temps toutefois, il réintroduisit une dimension épistémologique originale, s'écartant par là de son programme psychologique initial
  •  12
    La paille et la poutre: notes sur l'éthique de la condamnation morale
    Studia Philosophica 52 (n/a): 173-182. 1993.
    We often have judgments of moral condemnation on our fellow men. When we take seriously our individual and collective experience of moral judgment, we realize, however, that, in order to be properly brought to bear, judgments of moral condemnation must satisfy certain standards that are most often implicit. These norms form what we will call an "ethics of moral condemnation". Once unveiled, these standards surprise us with their rigor.
  •  454
    Bergson, truth-making, and the retrograde movement of the true
    Philosophical Papers Dedicated to Kevin Mulligan. 2011.
    Henri Bergson (1859-1941) was one of the main exponents of evolutionary thinking in the later nineteenth and early twentieth century. He gave that kind of thinking an unprecedented metaphysical turn. In consequence of his versatility he also encountered the notion of truth-making, which he connected with his ever-present concerns about time and duration. Eager to stress the dimension of radical change and of novelty in the nature of things, he rejected (in one form) what he called “the retrograd…Read more
  •  30
    Reid and Lehrer
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 40 (1): 135-147. 1991.
    The contrast between Thomas Reid's epistemological concerns and a common core of the classical approach to epistemology is the following one: Reid abandons the classical use for criteria of knowledge and pushes the problem of the justification of beliefs to the level of the mental faculties from which the beliefs arise. A similar shift plays various roles in Keith Lehrer's coherentist epistemology. However, this shift raises several difficulties: (i) the impact of epistemological concerns on act…Read more
  •  6
    Nécessaire sagesse? Essai sur l'assignation des valeurs
    Studia Philosophica 47 (n/a): 87-97. 1988.
    The article deals with the problem of the so-called “axiological neutrality” which characterizes modern science. Starting from a psychological conception of intrinsic value as that which is perceived worth being pursued, the author first shows that science can study values only indirectly. There are two senses in which science must remain axiologically neutral: on the one hand, it must avoid all ontological evaluation of its objects (ontological neutrality); on the other hand, it must keep separ…Read more
  •  12
    Jan MAREJKO, "Le territoire métaphysique" (review)
    Revue de Théologie Et de Philosophie 123 (n/a): 111. 1991.
    A critical review of Jan Marejko’s Le territoire métaphysique (1989), showing how this work proposes, on an anthropological and historical ground, a general interpretation of the moral and political condition of modern man.
  •  19
    The article proposes a comparison between the critique that Antoine Arnault (1612-1694) raises against Malebranche’s views on perception and the critique that Thomas Reid (1710-1796) moves against the theory of ideas defended by Berkeley and Hume. Both Arnault and Reid advocate a position according to which our perceptions allow us to have direct knowledge of material objects existing independently of us and not only of representations of them. Arnault proposes different arguments to refute Male…Read more
  •  4
    P. Lucier: "Empirisme logique et langage religieux" (review)
    Revue de Théologie Et de Philosophie 111 (n/a): 324. 1979.
    A review of Pierre Lucier’s Empirisme logique et langage religieux (1976). The work compares the interpretations of religious language provided by R.B. Braithwaite (who advocates the emotivist interpretation characteristic of logical positivism), of R.M. Hare (who proposes a “transcendental” interpretation seeing in religious language the acknowledgment of an order making possible both moral action and scientific research), and of I.T. Ramsay (who, against logical positivists, defend the possibi…Read more
  •  13
    La psychologie politique d’Adam Smith: Biais cognitifs et différences sociales dans la Théorie des sentiments moraux
    Studia Philosophica: Jahrbuch Der Schweizerischen Philosoph Ischen Gesellschaft, Annuaire de la Société Suisse de Philosphie  68 207-218. 2009.
    In his Theory of moral Sentiments , Adam Smith does not deal only with interpersonal moral issues. He also addresses some economic and political consequences that tie with his analysis of ‘sympathy’. Interestingly, these socially relevant outcomes do not feature as products of sympathy proper, but rather as byproducts of certain ‘irregularities’ or biases which affect the way sympathy actually works. The stability of a political society through a system of ‘ranks’ which are spontaneously granted…Read more
  •  11
    Concorde philosophique et réduplication chez Leibniz
    Studia Philosophica 66 211-220. 2007.
    Leibniz presents himself, especially in his late correspondence with Remond, as a concordist: in other philosophical views, even distant and ancient ones, he sets out to discover «traces of truth» that are already present there. According to the concordist programme, Leibniz claims, philosophers are right in what they affi rm, and wrong in what they deny. This paradoxical asymmetry is given a logical explanation in the paper, in connection with the topic of «reduplication», i. e. the introductio…Read more
  •  18
    This book’s review discusses the reinterpretation of Kant’s transcendental philosophy offered by Ronald Harri Wettstein. In the wake of K.O. Apel and J. Habermas, Kant is interpreted in the light of J.L. Austin’s theory of speech acts. The most original part of the book is chapter 3, in which Wettstein offers an unkantian theory of permitted lie, to which belong diplomacy, politeness, and discretion.
  •  5
    Obligation et connaissance
    Revue de Théologie Et de Philosophie 123 (n/a): 1. 1991.
    In the concrete exercise of practical reason, certain pieces of knowledge are required: they relate to the obligations to which the agent is committed (according to the deontological orientation in practical philosophy), to the actions themselves, as well as to the situations in which the agent operates. It appears that these pieces of knowledge are themselves required by what may be called here “second-order obligations”. The purpose of the article is to identify the place of these obligations …Read more
  •  8
    "J. Schlanger": Une théorie du savoir (review)
    Revue de Théologie Et de Philosophie 112 (n/a): 316. 1980.
    A review of Jacques Schlanger’s Une théorie du savoir (1978): a positivist account of the nature of knowledge, focusing on the relation to objectivity, with elements from systems theory.
  •  21
    The article proposes a comparison between the critique that Antoine Arnault (1612-1694) raises against Malebranche’s views on perception and the critique that Thomas Reid (1710-1796) moves against the theory of ideas defended by Berkeley and Hume. Both Arnault and Reid advocate a position according to which our perceptions allow us to have direct knowledge of material objects existing independently of us and not only of representations of them. Arnault proposes different arguments to refute Male…Read more
  •  5
    Q. Skinner: "The Foundations of Modern Political Thought" (review)
    Revue de Théologie Et de Philosophie 113 (n/a): 199. 1981.
    A review of Qu. Skinner’s The Foundations of Modern Political Thought (1978), emphasizing Skinner’s two main interpretative tenets: the importance of the roman stoic sources for Renaissance political thought, and the significance of roman right and of late scholastic moral and political philosophy (which developed the idea of social contract) for the Reform.
  •  64
    L’Individuation selon Brentano
    Philosophiques 26 (2). 1999.
    Brentano, expert et continuateur de l’ontologie aristotélicienne, traite du problème métaphysique de l’individuation dans un petit nombre d’écrits . Il retient pour ce problème une solution ordinairement rejetée, l’individuation par le lieu . À ce titre, il occupe une position originale. La notion de lieu, cependant, tout comme plus généralement la notion de l’accident, ressort tout à fait transformée des analyses de Brentano : le lieu devient une détermination substantielle, non accidentelle, d…Read more
  •  32
    The part‐whole and element‐system relations are usually not given a temporal interpretation. Taking a thesis of Father Bochenski as a starting point , the author first gives an adequate temporal interpretation of this thesis. Then, he shows that a divergence arises, in non‐static systems, between the system itself and the mereological sum corresponding to it at a certain instant. Therefore, any reductionism has to confront the generally neglected problem of this divergence. Résumé Les relations …Read more
  •  18
    Dugald Stewart's Original Letter on James Beattie's Essay on Truth, 1805–1806
    with Claire Etchegaray, Knud Haakonssen, David Stauffer, and Paul Wood
    History of European Ideas 38 (1): 103-121. 2012.
    The letters published here belong to the ‘Fonds Pierre Prevost’ held by the Library of Geneva. Our presentation of the letters is modelled on that of the published correspondences of Adam Smith and Thomas Reid. Our aim in transcribing the letters that follow has been to establish a clean and reliable text with minimal editorial intervention. We have made no attempt to normalise the spellings, capitalisation, and apparently aberrant usage found in the letters or to modernise the punctuation, and …Read more
  •  27
    «S'oublier soi-même»?
    Revue Philosophique De Louvain 107 (4): 637-646. 2009.
    At the end of the XVIIth century Nicholas Malebranche intervened in the «quietist dispute» in his Treatise on the Love of God (1697). This short treatise presents an anti-quietist standpoint based on the philosopher’s systematic analyses in the fields of theology and of psychology of the feelings and of the will. This article shows how Malebranche takes up the challenge of quietism, the logical heart of which, here reconstituted rigorously, is found in other moral philosophies. The requirement o…Read more
  •  13
    In his treatise, Hume wanted, at first, to release a purely psychological and naturalistic conception of belief, and thus to exclude evaluation by a normative epistemology. In a second time, however, he reintroduced an original epistemological dimension, thereby departing from his initial psychological program.
  •  35
    L'idée d'une doctrine cohérentiste de la justification épistémique
    Revue de Théologie Et de Philosophie 129 (2): 127-139. 1997.
    In the philosophical tradition marked by Descartes and empiricism, the idea of epistemic justification was most often seen in terms of construction on foundations that would be as many immediately justified starting points. The article exposes a completely different approach to the question, due to the philosopher Keith Lehrer. In this approach the epistemic justification derives from a coherence relationship between beliefs that are never immediately justified starting points. What is then deci…Read more
  •  4
    A. Gurwitsch: "Leibniz - Philosophie des Panlogismus" (review)
    Revue de Théologie Et de Philosophie 27 (n/a): 355. 1977.
    A review of Aron Gurwitsch’s Philosophie des Panlogismus (1974), which reads Leibniz’s metaphysics as a form of panlogicism. Leibniz’s metaphysics is not only derivable from his logic (Couturat, Russell), but is itself a form of logic, all the way down until reaching the level of the phenomena.