•  587
    The reference class problem is your problem too
    Synthese 156 (3): 563--585. 2007.
    The reference class problem arises when we want to assign a probability to a proposition (or sentence, or event) X, which may be classified in various ways, yet its probability can change depending on how it is classified. The problem is usually regarded as one specifically for the frequentist interpretation of probability and is often considered fatal to it. I argue that versions of the classical, logical, propensity and subjectivist interpretations also fall prey to their own variants of the r…Read more
  •  55
    Probability—A Philosophical Overview
    In Bonnie Gold & Roger Simons (eds.), Proof and Other Dilemmas: Mathematics and Philosophy, Mathematical Association of America. pp. 323. 2008.
  •  68
    Is Strict Coherence Coherent?
    Dialectica 66 (3): 411-424. 2012.
    Bayesians have a seemingly attractive account of rational credal states in terms of coherence. An agent's set of credences are synchronically coherent just in case they conform to the probability calculus. Some Bayesians impose a further putative coherence constraint called regularity: roughly, if X is possible, then it is assigned positive probability. I look at two versions of regularity – logical and metaphysical – and I canvass various defences of it as a rationality norm. Combining regulari…Read more
  •  191
    Conditional Probability Is the Very Guide of Life
    In Kyburg Jr, E. Henry & Mariam Thalos (eds.), Probability is the Very Guide of Life: The Philosophical Uses of Chance, Open Court. pp. 183--203. 2003.
    in Probability is the Very Guide of Life: The Philosophical Uses of Chance, eds. Henry Kyburg, Jr. and Mariam Thalos, Open Court. Abridged version in Proceedings of the International Society for Bayesian Analysis 2002.
  •  276
    Vexing expectations
    with Harris Nover
    Mind 113 (450): 237-249. 2004.
    We introduce a St. Petersburg-like game, which we call the ‘Pasadena game’, in which we toss a coin until it lands heads for the first time. Your pay-offs grow without bound, and alternate in sign (rewards alternate with penalties). The expectation of the game is a conditionally convergent series. As such, its terms can be rearranged to yield any sum whatsoever, including positive infinity and negative infinity. Thus, we can apparently make the game seem as desirable or undesirable as we want, s…Read more
  •  141
    Arguments For—Or Against—Probabilism?
    In Franz Huber & Christoph Schmidt-Petri (eds.), Degrees of belief, Springer. pp. 229--251. 2009.
    Four important arguments for probabilism—the Dutch Book, representation theorem, calibration, and gradational accuracy arguments—have a strikingly similar structure. Each begins with a mathematical theorem, a conditional with an existentially quantified consequent, of the general form: if your credences are not probabilities, then there is a way in which your rationality is impugned. Each argument concludes that rationality requires your credences to be probabilities. I contend that each argumen…Read more
  •  324
    Ramsey + Moore = God
    Analysis 67 (2): 170-172. 2007.
    Frank Ramsey (1931) wrote: If two people are arguing 'if p will q?' and both are in doubt as to p, they are adding p hypothetically to their stock of knowledge and arguing on that basis about q. We can say that they are fixing their degrees of belief in q given p. Let us take the first sentence the way it is often taken, as proposing the following test for the acceptability of an indicative conditional: ‘If p then q’ is acceptable to a subject S iff, were S to accept p and consider q, S would ac…Read more
  •  215
    According to finite frequentism, the probability of an attribute A in a finite reference class B is the relative frequency of actual occurrences of A within B. I present fifteen arguments against this position.
  •  98
    In Defense of Hume’s Balancing of Probabilities in the Miracles Argument
    Southwest Philosophy Review 11 (1): 111-118. 1995.
    I vindicate Hume’s argument against belief in miracle reports against a prevalent objection. Hume has us balance the probability of a miracle’s occurrence against the probability of its being falsely attested to, and argues that the latter must inevitably be the greater; thus, reason requires us to reject any miracle report. The "flaw" in this reasoning, according to Butler and many others, is that it proves too much--it counsels us to never believe historians, newspaper reports of lottery resul…Read more
  •  29
    Bayes or Bust? (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 60 (3): 707-711. 2000.
    A battered old philosophy of science vehicle heads west towards the Bayesian gold fields. Odd bits of junk are tied to the roof. In the rear window is a sign that reads “Bayes or Bust!” So far the story is not new. But at the wheel is a famous race car driver who has accelerated out of Newtonian space-time and decelerated back again.. Who could resist going along for the ride? We couldn’t—and you shouldn’t either.
  •  141
    Unexpected Expectations
    Mind 123 (490): 533-567. 2014.
    A decade ago, Harris Nover and I introduced the Pasadena game, which we argued gives rise to a new paradox in decision theory even more troubling than the St Petersburg paradox. Gwiazda's and Smith's articles in this volume both offer revisionist solutions. I critically engage with both articles. They invite reflections on a number of deep issues in the foundations of decision theory, which I hope to bring out. These issues include: some ways in which orthodox decision theory might be supplement…Read more
  •  355
    The Cable Guy paradox
    Analysis 65 (2): 112-119. 2005.
    The Cable Guy is coming. You have to be home in order for him to install your new cable service, but to your chagrin he cannot tell you exactly when he will come. He will definitely come between 8.a.m. and 4 p.m. tomorrow, but you have no more information than that. I offer to keep you company while you wait. To make things more interesting, we decide now to bet on the Cable Guy’s arrival time. We subdivide the relevant part of the day into two 4-hour long intervals, ‘morning’: (8, 12], and ‘aft…Read more
  •  88
    Probabilities of counterfactuals and counterfactual probabilities
    Journal of Applied Logic 12 (3): 235-251. 2014.
    Probabilities figure centrally in much of the literature on the semantics of conditionals. I find this surprising: it accords a special status to conditionals that other parts of language apparently do not share. I critically discuss two notable ‘probabilities first’ accounts of counterfactuals, due to Edgington and Leitgeb. According to Edgington, counterfactuals lack truth values but have probabilities. I argue that this combination gives rise to a number of problems. According to Leitgeb, cou…Read more