•  28
    Titmuss revisited: from tax credits to markets
    Journal of Medical Ethics 38 (8): 461-462. 2012.
    Petersen and Lippert-Rasmussen argue that persons who decide to be organ donors should receive a tax break, and then defend their view against eight possible objections. However, they misunderstand the Titmuss-style concerns that might be raised against their proposal. This does not mean that it should be rejected, but, instead, that when it is reconfigured to meet the Titmuss-style charges against it, they should support legalizing markets in human organs rather than merely offering tax breaks …Read more
  •  27
    The point of sale
    The Philosophers' Magazine 59 (59): 115-118. 2012.
  •  24
    The Myth of Semiotic Arguments in Democratic Theory and How This Exposes Problems with Peer Review
    International Journal of Applied Philosophy 35 (1): 13-29. 2021.
    In a recent series or books and articles Jason Brennan and Peter M. Jaworski (writing both together and separately) have developed criticisms of what they term “semiotic” arguments. They hold that these arguments are widely used both to criticize markets in certain goods, to defend democracy, and criticize epistocracy. Their work on semiotics is now widely (and approvingly) cited. In this paper I argue that there is no reason to believe that any defenders of democracy or critics of epistocracy h…Read more
  •  1
    The Future of Practical Philosophy
    International Journal of Philosophical Practice 2 (2): 38-45. 2004.
    Over the last two decades the practice of applied philosophy has undergone re­surgence. It is now common for philosophers to sit on ethics committees in hospitals, or to provide ethical advice to businesses, and many universities and colleges now offer courses in practical philosophy. Despite this, practical philosophy is subject to increasing criticism, with persons charging that (1) it is philosophically shallow, and (2) it has little to offer persons grappling with concrete ethical problems, …Read more
  •  23
    The Ethics and Politics of Blood Plasma Donation
    International Journal of Applied Philosophy 34 (1): 89-103. 2020.
    Legal prohibitions on the financial compensation of donors are frequently justified by appealing either to concerns about patient safety or to concerns about the putatively unethical nature of such compensation. But jurisdictions that legally prohibit the financial compensation of donors routinely import plasma that has been collected from financially compensated donors—and they do so knowing its origins. I outline some possible ways in which this puzzle could be resolved and find them all wanti…Read more
  •  3
    The Central Value of Philosophical Counseling
    International Journal of Philosophical Practice 1 (2): 1-9. 2002.
    The title of this paper is deliberately ambiguous. It could refer either to the central val­ue that philosophical counseling has for philosophy in general, or else it could refer to something (such as personal autonomy, or personal well-being) that philosophical counselors believe to be of value, and that they are able to help their clients pursue. In fact, this paper will be addressing both of these topics in order to demonstrate the links that hold between them, and, in so doing, will attempt …Read more
  •  21
    The Carelessness of Affordable Care
    Hastings Center Report 42 (5): 24-27. 2012.
    The Affordable Care Act has been touted as a long‐overdue remedy for what is perceived to be the chronic problem of large numbers of Americans living without adequate health insurance. While much of the discussion of the ACA has focused on its legality, it should also be assessed on the basis of its economic implications and its moral acceptability. On its face, the ACA appears to do well on both counts. Given that the uninsured often secure their health care from expensive emergency room treatm…Read more
  •  33
    Two (Weak) Cheers for Markets in Votes
    Philosophia 46 (1): 223-239. 2018.
    This paper offers the first moral defense of markets in votes in a democratic electoral system based on majority rule where there are no moral restrictions on how votes can be cast. In Part 1 I outline the type of vote buying that I defend in this paper, and defend my methodological assumption. In Part 2 I criticize Freiman’s arguments for legalizing vote buying. In Part 3 I outline and reply to some responses that could be made to my criticisms of Freiman’s arguments. In Part 4 I draw from the …Read more
  •  93
    The Case Against the Case for Colonialism
    International Journal of Applied Philosophy 32 (1): 19-32. 2018.
    In a recent paper entitled “The Case for Colonialism” Bruce Gilley argued that Western colonialism was “as a general rule” both beneficial to those subject to it and considered by them to be legitimate. He then advocated for a return to the Western colonization of the Third World. Gilley’s article provoked a furious response, with calls for its retraction being followed by the resignation of much of the publishing journal’s editorial board. In this paper I note that Gilley’s article meets none o…Read more
  •  52
    The Case Against the Case for Colonialism
    International Journal of Applied Philosophy 32 (1): 19-32. 2018.
    In a recent paper entitled “The Case for Colonialism” Bruce Gilley argued that Western colonialism was “as a general rule” both beneficial to those subject to it and considered by them to be legitimate. He then advocated for a return to the Western colonization of the Third World. Gilley’s article provoked a furious response, with calls for its retraction being followed by the resignation of much of the publishing journal’s editorial board. In this paper I note that Gilley’s article meets none o…Read more
  •  29
    Stefaan Cuypers, self-identity and personal autonomy
    Journal of Value Inquiry 37 (2): 259-265. 2003.
  •  31
    Satz and Semiotics
    International Journal of Applied Philosophy 33 (2): 243-257. 2019.
    Jason Brennan and Peter M. Jaworski have recently developed an argument against semiotic objections to markets. They argue that all such semiotic arguments are unsound because they fail to recognize that the meaning of market transactions is a contingent socially-constructed fact. They attribute this type of argument to Debra Satz. This paper argues both that Brennan and Jaworski are mistaken to attribute this particular semiotic objection to Satz and that they are mistaken to attribute to her a…Read more
  •  23
    Stoic Anxiolytics Revisited
    International Journal of Applied Philosophy 25 (1): 115-117. 2011.
  •  13
    In 'Stakes and Kidneys' the author discusses various ethical issues surrounding the international trade in human organs.
  •  23
    Social Autonomy and Family-Based Informed Consent
    Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 44 (5): 621-639. 2019.
    The Western focus on personal autonomy as the normative basis for securing persons’ consent to their treatment renders this autonomy-based approach to informed consent vulnerable to the charge that it is based on an overly atomistic understanding of the person. This leads to a puzzle: how does this generally-accepted atomistic understanding of the person fits with the emphasis on familial consent that occurs when family members are provided with the opportunity to veto a prospective donor’s wish…Read more
  •  35
    Reappraising the Role of Autonomy in Medical Ethics
    Professional Ethics, a Multidisciplinary Journal 8 (1): 19-33. 2000.
  •  33
  •  41
    Reassessing Academic Plagiarism
    Journal of Academic Ethics 22 (2): 211-230. 2024.
    I argue that wrong of plagiarism does not primarily stem from the plagiarist’s illicit misappropriation of academic credit from the person she plagiarized. Instead, plagiarism is wrongful to the degree to which it runs counter to the purpose of academic work. Given that this is to increase knowledge and further understanding plagiarism will be wrongful to the extent that it impedes the achievement of these ends. This account of the wrong of plagiarism has two surprising (and related) implication…Read more
  •  61
    Promises to the Dead
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 90 81-103. 2021.
    Many people attempt to give meaning to their lives by pursuing projects that they believe will bear fruit after they have died. Knowing that their death will preclude them from protecting or promoting such projects people who draw meaning from them will often attempt to secure their continuance by securing promises from others to serve as their caretakers after they die. But those who rely on such are faced with a problem: None of the four major accounts that have been developed to explain direc…Read more
  •  6
    In a recent article (“The current state of the platelet supply in the US and proposed options to decrease the risk of critical shortages”) published in _Transfusion,_ Stubbs et al. have argued that platelet donors should be paid. Dodd et al. have argued against this proposal, supporting their response with survey data that shows that blood donors (and by extension platelet donors) and potential platelet donors are uninterested in receiving incentives to encourage them to donate. Instead, argue D…Read more
  •  26
    Public Moralities and Markets in Organs
    Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 39 (3): 223-227. 2014.
    Schweda and Schicktanz argue that the debate over the ethics of using financial incentives to procure human transplant organs rests on socioempirical premises that need to be critically assessed. They contend that once this is achieved a completely new perspective on the debate should be adopted, with organ donation being viewed primarily as a reciprocal social interaction between donor and recipient. This paper challenges this conclusion, arguing that rather than supporting a new perspective on…Read more
  •  135
    Privacy and Autonomy: A Reappraisal
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 40 (4): 587-604. 2002.
  •  17
    Organs: tradable, but not necessarily inheritable
    Journal of Medical Ethics 40 (1): 62-62. 2014.
    Teck Chuan Voo and Soren Holm argue that “organs should be inheritable if they were to be socially and legally recognised as tradable property.”1 To support this view they first observe that “…legal recognition of objects as property… opens up the possibility of the legal recognition of the survival of the property rights and their inheritability after the death of the source/owner, even if those rights are intimately bound with the person.”1 They also note that if organs are tradable property t…Read more
  •  12
    Develops a taxonomy of the positions that are held by critics of markets. Taylor argues that market debates derailed because they were conducted in accord with market, rather than academic, norms--and that this demonstrates that market thinking should not govern academic research.
  •  48
    Moral Repugnance, Moral Distress, and Organ Sales
    Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 40 (3): 312-327. 2015.
    Many still oppose legalizing markets in human organs on the grounds that they are morally repugnant. I will argue in this paper that the repugnance felt by some persons towards sales of human organs is insufficient to justify their prohibition. Yet this rejection of the view that markets in human organs should be prohibited because some persons find them to be morally repugnant does not imply that persons’ feelings of distress at the possibility of organ sales are irrational. Eduardo Rivera-Lope…Read more
  •  15
    Market-Based Reforms in Health Care Are Both Practical and Morally Sound
    Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 40 (3): 537-546. 2012.
    In this paper I argue that the free-market provision of health care is both practical and morally sound, and is superior in both respects to its provision by the State. The State provision of health care will be inefficient compared to its free-market alternative. It will thus provide less health care to persons for the same amount of expenditure, and so save fewer lives and alleviate less suffering for two reasons: state actors have no incentive to husband their resources effectively, and that …Read more