•  38
  •  1
    Making discourse ethical: The lessons of Aristotle's Rhetoric'
    Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 5 73-96. 1989.
  •  45
    The Moral Virtue and the Two Sides of Energeia
    Ancient Philosophy 9 (2): 293-312. 1989.
  •  58
    Aristotle's "De Interpretatione": Contradiction and Dialectic (review)
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 36 (3): 459-460. 1998.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Aristotle’s “De Interpretatione”: Contradiction and Dialectic by C. W. A. WhitakerEugene GarverC. W. A. Whitaker, Aristotle’s “De Interpretatione”: Contradiction and Dialectic. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1996. Pp. x + 235. Cloth, $60.00.Traditionally, the De Interpretatione is placed in the Organon between the Categories and the Prior Analytics. Where the Categories is about single terms and the Analytics about inferences, …Read more
  •  28
    Spinoza's "Ethics"
    Philosophy and Theology 24 (2): 155-190. 2012.
    The Preface to Part 4 of Spinoza’s Ethics claims that we all desire to formulate a model of human nature. I show how that model serves the same function in ethics as the creed or articles of faith do in the Tractatus Theologico-Politicus, the function of allowing the imagination to provide a simularcrrum of rationality for finite, practical human beings.
  •  38
    Good Arguments (review)
    Teaching Philosophy 10 (4): 366-367. 1987.
  •  41
    Can virtue be bought?
    Philosophy and Rhetoric 37 (4): 353-382. 2004.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Can Virtue Be Bought?Eugene Garver1. The problem: Epistemic elitism or cognitive dominanceDemocracy and rationality can be enemies. Superior intelligence and information can silence people, and the voices of reason can be drowned out by anti-intellectual populism. Given the dearth of both democracy and rationality in contemporary American politics, I hope that each can be fortified by association with the other, but I don't think tha…Read more
  •  18
    Paradigms and princes
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 17 (1): 21-47. 1987.
  •  60
    Why Pluralism Now?
    The Monist 73 (3): 388-410. 1990.
    We are all pluralists today. Ecumenism—in religion, in literary criticism, in philosophy—seems obligatory, although what it requires and how sincere its professions are both are open to dispute. Some people are reluctant pluraliste, disappointed with the inescapable fact of plurality, while others embrace it with delight and hope. Everyone is a pluralist—even people whom no one else thinks of as pluralists assert that they are themselves pluralists. It takes no high theory but brute observation …Read more
  •  46
  • Machiavelli and the History of Prudence
    Philosophy and Rhetoric 24 (1): 73-76. 1991.
  •  10
    The Ethical Criticism of Reasoning
    Philosophy and Rhetoric 31 (2). 1998.
  •  13
    How to Develop Ideas
    Teaching Philosophy 6 (2): 97-102. 1983.
  •  21
    Euthyphro Prosecutes a Human Rights Violation
    Philosophy and Literature 38 (2): 510-527. 2014.
    Socrates encounters Euthyphro as both are on their way to court, Socrates as a defendant against charges of blasphemy and Euthyphro as a prosecutor of his father for negligently causing the death of a slave—a human rights violation. While I argue that piety and pollution supply a productive way of thinking about human rights crime and punishment, Euthyphro is a very troubling model for the human rights prosecutor, since he is an almost paradigmatically unattractive character. Reading the Euthyph…Read more
  •  22
    Spinoza and the Discovery of Morality
    History of Philosophy Quarterly 23 (4). 2006.
  •  84
    What is the good life? Posing this question today would likely elicit very different answers. Some might say that the good life means doing good—improving one’s community and the lives of others. Others might respond that it means doing well—cultivating one’s own abilities in a meaningful way. But for Aristotle these two distinct ideas—doing good and doing well—were one and the same and could be realized in a single life. In Confronting Aristotle’s Ethics, Eugene Garver examines how we can draw …Read more
  •  62
    Aristotle's Rhetoric: An Art of Character
    University of Chicago Press. 1994.
    In this major contribution to philosophy and rhetoric, Eugene Garver shows how Aristotle integrates logic and virtue in his great treatise, the _Rhetoric._ He raises and answers a central question: can there be a civic art of rhetoric, an art that forms the character of citizens? By demonstrating the importance of the _Rhetoric_ for understanding current philosophical problems of practical reason, virtue, and character, Garver has written the first work to treat the _Rhetoric_ as philosophy and …Read more
  •  26
  •  50
    Aristotle's genealogy of morals
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 44 (4): 471-492. 1984.
  •  58
    Selected Issues in Logic and Communication (review)
    Teaching Philosophy 11 (4): 369-371. 1988.
  •  4
    Good Arguments (review)
    Teaching Philosophy 10 (4): 366-367. 1987.
  •  7
    Aristotle's "Rhetoric": Philosophical Essays (review) (review)
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 33 (4): 680-683. 1995.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:680 JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY 33:4 OCTOBER 1995 cal advance over the criticisms of the Parmenidesas to say how the Theaetetusshould be called an "Eleatic" dialogue. The Sophist then reintroduces form, but in its epistemological aspect alone. Extensive use is made of the method of division, presented in the commentary as a rigorous method for precise definition, yet the Sophistfails to distinguish sophistry from philosophy.…Read more