•  13
  •  12
    Narratice, Rhetorical Argument, and Ethical Authority
    Law and Critique 10 (2): 117-146. 1999.
    The great challenge of rhetorical argument is to make discourse ethical without making it less logical. This challenge is of central importance throughout the full range of practical argument, and understanding the relation of the ethical to the logical is one of the principal contributions the humanities, in this case the study of rhetoric, can make to legal scholarship. Aristotle’s Rhetoric shows how arguments can be ethical and can create ethical relations between speaker and hearer. I intend…Read more
  •  12
    The Crito dramatizes the impossibility, and the indispensability, of persuasion sby locating it between two extremes, Socrates and the Laws, the truths of philosophy and the force of politics. The question is whether those two limits are themselves inside or outside rhetoric. Can philosophy persuade, ormust it always be an alternative sto persuasion? Socrates insists on ignoring the opinion, and the power, of the many, and so the Laws have to show themselves as different from the opinion of the …Read more
  •  10
    Spinoza and the Cunning of Imagination
    University of Chicago Press. 2018.
    Spinoza’s Ethics, and its project of proving ethical truths through the geometric method, have attracted and challenged readers for more than three hundred years. In Spinoza and the Cunning of Imagination, Eugene Garver uses the imagination as a guiding thread to this work. Other readers have looked at the imagination to account for Spinoza’s understanding of politics and religion, but this is the first inquiry to see it as central to the Ethics as a whole—imagination as a quality to be cultivat…Read more
  •  10
    The Ethical Criticism of Reasoning
    Philosophy and Rhetoric 31 (2). 1998.
  •  10
  •  10
  •  10
    Pluralism in theory and practice: Richard McKeon and American philosophy (edited book)
    with Richard Buchanan
    Vanderbilt University Press. 2000.
    Pluralism in Theory and Practice not only brings McKeon to the attention of contemporary philosophers and students; it also puts his theories into practice. Some of the essays explicate aspects of McKeon's thought or situate him in the context of American intellectual and practical engagement. Others take the concerns he raised as starting points for inquiries into urgent contemporary problems, or, in some cases, for reexamining McKeon's work as fertile ground for shaping the direction of new in…Read more
  •  9
    Colloquium 5
    Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 10 (1): 171-200. 1994.
  •  9
    Review of Peter Singer: Democracy and Disobedience (review)
    Ethics 86 (2): 175-179. 1976.
  •  9
    Colloquium 3
    Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 5 (1): 73-96. 1989.
  •  8
    Maimonides after 800 Years (review)
    Review of Metaphysics 62 (3): 661-662. 2009.
  •  8
    Review of Gene Sharp: The Politics of Nonviolent Action (review)
    Ethics 84 (3): 266-273. 1974.
  •  7
    Aristotle's "Rhetoric": Philosophical Essays (review) (review)
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 33 (4): 680-683. 1995.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:680 JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY 33:4 OCTOBER 1995 cal advance over the criticisms of the Parmenidesas to say how the Theaetetusshould be called an "Eleatic" dialogue. The Sophist then reintroduces form, but in its epistemological aspect alone. Extensive use is made of the method of division, presented in the commentary as a rigorous method for precise definition, yet the Sophistfails to distinguish sophistry from philosophy.…Read more
  •  6
    Politics V presents preserving and destroying the constitution as exhaustive alternatives, leaving no apparent room for improving the constitution. Aristotle claims that 'if we know the causes by which constitutions are destroyed we also know the causes by which they are preserved; for opposites create opposites, and destruction is the opposite of security' . The first seven chapters present the causes by which constitutions are destroyed, and then chapters 8 and 9 show the causes by which they …Read more
  •  4
    Good Arguments (review)
    Teaching Philosophy 10 (4): 366-367. 1987.
  •  4
    Aristotle's Politics V As An Example
    History of Political Thought 26 (2): 489-208. 2005.
    Virtuous people, unlike the rich and poor, do not form factions. What, then, is the role of philosophical argument within political argument? Politics V can be read as a handbook of practical advice that will help any rulers to stay in power, but it in fact develops a more subtle, and radical, role for philosophy in political argument. Like virtue, philosophy cannot be partisan, but the philosophical understanding of faction that Aristotle presents here makes its own contribution to political st…Read more
  •  3
    8 Rhetoric, Hermeneutics, and Prudence in the Interpretation of the Constitution
    In eds Walter Jost and Michael J. Hyde (ed.), Rhetoric and Hermeneutics in Our Time: A Reader, Yale University Press. pp. 171-195
  •  3
    Truth in Politics- Ethical Argument, Ethical Knowledge, and Ethical Truth
    Quest - and African Journal of Philosophy 16 (1-2): 220-237. 2002.
  •  1
    Making discourse ethical: The lessons of Aristotle's Rhetoric'
    Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 5 73-96. 1989.
  • Aristotle's "Rhetoric": An Art of Character
    Philosophy and Rhetoric 29 (4): 436-440. 1996.
  • Pluralism in Theory and Practice: Richard McKeon and American Philosophy
    with Richard Buchanan
    Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 37 (3): 436-441. 2001.
  • Machiavelli and the History of Prudence
    Philosophy and Rhetoric 24 (1): 73-76. 1991.