•  38
    Amidst the progress being made in the various (sub-)disciplines of the behavioural and brain sciences a somewhat neglected subject is the problem of how everything fits into one world and, derivatively, how the relation between different levels of discourse should be understood and to what extent different levels, domains, approaches, or disciplines are autonomous or dependent. In this paper I critically review the most recent proposals to specify the nature of interdiscourse relations, focusing…Read more
  •  36
    Whatever seems right to me is right
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 22 (6): 973-973. 1999.
    It is argued that given the task Palmer sets himself, there are no constraints on his colour experiences whatsoever.
  •  36
    Out of the Ge-stell? The Role of the East in Heidegger’s das andere Denken
    with Lin Ma
    Philosophy East and West 64 (3): 527-562. 2014.
    Modern technology (Technik, la technique) has constituted the gears on which the wheels of the modern world keep turning. The later Heidegger devotes sustained reflection to this unprecedented phenomenon in human history. It is notable that, compared with other figures from twentieth-century continental philosophy, Heidegger has served as the most frequent reference point in current philosophy of technology (Technikphilosophie). This field of philosophy came into being after the so-called empiri…Read more
  •  36
    The world: An unruly mess (review)
    Foundations of Chemistry 3 (3): 251-262. 2001.
  •  36
    Theories, Technologies, Instrumentalities of Color: Anthropological and Historiographic Perspectives
    with Debi Roberson, Ian Davies, Jules Davidoff, Arnold Henselmans, Don Dedrick, Alan Costall, Angus Gellatly, Paul Whittle, Patrick Heelan, Rainer Mausfeld, Thomas Johansen, Hans Kraml, Joseph Wachelder, Friedrich Steinle, and Ton Derksen
    Upa. 2002.
    Theories, Technologies, Instrumentalities of Color is the outcome of a workshop, held in Leuven, Belgium, in May 2000
  •  35
    Epistemische deugden en hun verantwoording
    Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 60 (2): 243-268. 1998.
    In this paper I argue that all proposals for demarcation criteria distinguishing between scientific and non-scientific knowledge, have failed. Moreover, there is not a single set of epistemic virtues that characterizes 'good' knowledge, nor is there such a set that characterizes science. There are many different epistemic virtues and no universal rules about how they are to be applied in particular cases. Different virtues may dominate in different knowledge domains. In the 'same' domain there a…Read more
  •  35
    On The Philosophy of Chemistry
    with H. Vermeeren
    Philosophy Research Archives 7 501-552. 1981.
    While in the research area known,as ’philosophy of science' there is a growing interest in separate disciplines of the empirical sciences, applied sciences and even technologies, one can find hardly any reference to the discipline of chemistry other than some preliminary discussions of chemical concepts or studies concerning the rational reconstruction of the history of chemistry. No analyses, which might be called 'philosophy of chemistry’ can be found to date. It is hoped that this review pape…Read more
  •  32
    Kleur: Een exosomatisch orgaan?
    with Barbara Saunders
    Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 64 (2): 299-324. 2002.
    According to the state of the art in psychology and philosophy, colour sensations are located in a 'quality space'. This space has three dimensions: hue , saturation , and brightness. This space is structured further via a small number of primitive hues or landmark colours, usually four or six . It has also been suggested that there are eleven semantic universals — the six colours previously mentioned plus orange, pink, brown, purple, and grey. Against the standard view, we argue that colour mig…Read more
  •  32
    Revisiting W ittgenstein on Family Resemblance and Colour(s)
    with Lin Ma
    Philosophical Investigations 39 (3): 254-280. 2016.
    We argue that all general concepts are family resemblance concepts. These include concepts introduced by ostension, such as colour(s). Concepts of colour and of each of the specific colours are family resemblance concepts because similarities concerning an open‐ended range of colour or of appearance features crop up and disappear. After discussing the notion of “same colour” and Wittgenstein's use of the phrase “our colours”, we suggest family resemblance concepts in one tradition can often be e…Read more
  •  31
    Conventions In Naming
    Philosophy Research Archives 8 243-277. 1982.
    Conventions in the use of names are discussed, particularly names of linguistic expressions. Also the reference of measure terms like ‘kg’ is discussed, and it is found analogous in important respects to expression names. Some new light is shed on the token-type distinction. Applications to versions of the liar paradox are shown. The use of quotation marks is critically examined.
  •  30
    A Theory of Interpretation for Comparative and Chinese Philosophy
    with Lin Ma
    Dao: A Journal of Comparative Philosophy 15 (4): 575-589. 2016.
    Why should interpretation of conceptual schemes and practices across traditions work at all? In this paper we present the following necessary conditions of possibility for interpretation in comparative and Chinese philosophy: the interpreter must presuppose that there are mutually recognizable human practices; the interpreter must presuppose that “the other” is, on the whole, sincere, consistent, and right; the interpreter must be committed to certain epistemic virtues. Some of these necessary c…Read more
  •  30
    Telematic Life Forms
    Techné: Research in Philosophy and Technology 4 (3): 208-219. 1999.
    status: published.
  •  29
    Which colour space(s) is Shepard talking about?
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 24 (4): 661-662. 2001.
    Contra Shepard we argue, first, that his presentation of a three-dimensional representational (psychological or phenomenal) colour space is at odds with many results in colour science, and, second, that there is insufficient evidence for Shepard's stronger claim that the three-dimensionality of colour perception has resulted from natural selection, moulded by the particulars of the solar spectrum and its variations. [Shepard].
  •  28
    The ethnocentricity of colour
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1): 53-54. 1992.
  •  25
    Ceteris paribus laws
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3): 584-585. 1992.
  •  24
    Colour is a culturalist category
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 28 (4): 507-508. 2005.
    Extrapolation of Steels & Belpaeme's (S&B) results show that colour is a culturalist category. Populations will only share the category of colour if it is built into the system. If “left to themselves” different populations may or may not stumble on the colour category. Populations that do not share a colour category may still be able to communicate in a wide variety of environments.
  •  23
    In this article, I look at those passages in the Zhuangzi usually associated with “uselessness.” I discuss in what way these passages may have been suggestive to Martin Heidegger to explain his ideas of the necessity of the other thinking and of the “waiting people” being entirely unusable to others. Then I make some brief comments concerning basic conditions of interpretation, using examples taken from the Zhuangzi passages discussed. These conditions include family resemblance across the board…Read more
  •  22
    Art and science as ways of worldmaking
    with Barbara Saunders
    In Paul Weingartner & Gerhard Schurz (eds.), Proceedings of the 11th International Wittgenstein Symposium, Hölder-pichler-tempsky. 1987.
  •  22
    Internal Realism, Truth and Charity
    Dialectica 42 (1): 37-44. 1988.
  •  20
    We
    Ethical Perspectives 6 (3): 268-276. 1999.
    Williams's comments raise the questions I'll here address: what sort of wes are there?, what goes with the 'we of science and logic'?, and what goes with the 'parochial us'? The quotations from Williams suggest that there are two wes, the contrastive and inclusive we.
  •  20
    Revisiting the Exchange between Zhuangzi and Huizi on Qing
    with Lin Ma
    Dao: A Journal of Comparative Philosophy 20 (1): 133-148. 2021.
    In this article we focus on the famous dialogue between Zhuangzi 莊子 and Huizi 惠子 concerning the question whether or not ren 人 (in particular the shengren 聖人) have qing 情. Most scholars have understood qing in this exchange as referring to “feelings” or “emotions.” We take issue with such readings. First, we demonstrate that, while Huizi probably understands qing as something like feelings or emotions, Zhuangzi’s view is that having qing is connected with making shifei 是非 judgments whereas having…Read more
  •  19
    Interpreting self-ascriptions
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (2): 393-395. 1995.
  •  19
    On the Interpreter’s Choices: Making Hermeneutic Relativity Explicit
    with Lin Ma
    Dao: A Journal of Comparative Philosophy 17 (4): 453-478. 2018.
    In this essay, we explore the various aspects of hermeneutic relativity that have rarely been explicitly discussed. Our notion of “hermeneutic relativity” can be seen as an extension, with significant revisions, of Gadamer’s notion of Vorurteil. It refers to various choices and constraints of the interpreter, including beliefs concerning the best way of doing philosophy, what criteria are to be used to evaluate competing interpretations, and so on. The interpreter cannot completely eliminate the…Read more
  •  18
    Discusses the conditions of possibility for intercultural and comparative philosophy, and for crosscultural communication at large. This innovative book explores the preconditions necessary for intercultural and comparative philosophy. Philosophical practices that involve at least two different traditions with no common heritage and whose languages have very different grammatical structure, such as Indo-Germanic languages and classical Chinese, are a particular focus. Lin Ma and Jaap van Brakel …Read more
  •  18
  •  18
    Modeling in Chemical Engineering
    Hyle 6 (2). 2000.
    Models underlying the use of similarity considerations, dimensionless numbers, and dimensional analysis in chemical engineering are discussed. Special attention is given to the many levels at which models and ceteris paribus conditions play a role and to the modeling of initial and boundary conditions. It is shown that both the laws or dimensionless number correlations and the systems to which they apply are models. More generally, no matter which model or description one picks out, what is bein…Read more
  •  17
    (Hard ernst) 126–132 corrigendum
    with Erik J. Olsson, Believing More, and U. Kriegel
    Erkenntnis 57 (1): 457-458. 2002.
  •  17
    A Theory of Interpretation for Comparative and Chinese Philosophy
    with Lin Ma
    Dao: A Journal of Comparative Philosophy 15 (4): 575-589. 2016.
    Why should interpretation of conceptual schemes and practices across traditions work at all? In this paper we present the following necessary conditions of possibility for interpretation in comparative and Chinese philosophy: the interpreter must presuppose that there are mutually recognizable human practices; the interpreter must presuppose that “the other” is, on the whole, sincere, consistent, and right; the interpreter must be committed to certain epistemic virtues. Some of these necessary c…Read more
  •  16
    Moral and political implications of pragmatism
    with Barbara3 Saunders
    Journal of Value Inquiry 23 (4): 259-274. 1989.
    status: published.