• PhilPapers
  • PhilPeople
  • PhilArchive
  • PhilEvents
  • PhilJobs
  • Sign in
PhilPeople
 
  • Sign in
  • News Feed
  • Find Philosophers
  • Departments
  • Radar
  • Help
 
profile-cover
Drag to reposition
profile picture

Francois Recanati

Institut Jean Nicod
  •  Home
  •  Publications
    190
    • Most Recent
    • Most Downloaded
    • Topics
  •  Events
    27
  •  News and Updates
    204

 More details
  • Institut Jean Nicod
    Department of Philosophy- CNRS
    Regular Faculty
  • All publications (190)
  •  6
    Reply to Frapolli
    Response to Frapolli's contribution in the proceedings of the Granada workshop
    Philosophy of LinguisticsIntentionality
  •  70
    Knowing that I See. Comments on Alex Byrne
    In Ijn Working Papers, . 2010.
    Response to Alex Byrne's paper 'Knowing what I see'.
    TransparencySelf-Consciousness in Experience
  •  142
    Mental Files: an Introduction
    with Michael Murez
    Review of Philosophy and Psychology 7 (2): 265-281. 2016.
    IntentionalityConcepts
  •  66
    Moderate relativism
    In Manuel Garcia-Carpintero & Max Koelbel (eds.), Relative Truth, Oxford University Press. pp. 41-62. 2006.
    In modal logic, propositions are evaluated relative to possible worlds. A proposition may be true relative to a world w, and false relative to another world w'. Relativism is the view that the relativization idea extends beyond possible worlds and modalities. Thus, in tense logic, propositions are evaluated relative to times. A proposition (e.g. the proposition that Socrates is sitting) may be true relative to a time t, and false relative to another time t'. In this paper I discuss, and attempt …Read more
    In modal logic, propositions are evaluated relative to possible worlds. A proposition may be true relative to a world w, and false relative to another world w'. Relativism is the view that the relativization idea extends beyond possible worlds and modalities. Thus, in tense logic, propositions are evaluated relative to times. A proposition (e.g. the proposition that Socrates is sitting) may be true relative to a time t, and false relative to another time t'. In this paper I discuss, and attempt to rebut, two classical objections to Relativism. The first objection, due to Frege, is the objection from incompleteness. I distinguish two possible relativist responses to that objection, one of which corresponds to the view I actually defend : Moderate Relativism. The second objection is due to Mark Richard, who argued that the objects of belief cannot be relativistic. I show that that objection can be met within the Moderate Relativist framework. In the last section, I deal with special forms of disagreement that have loomed large in recent discussions of Relativism.
    Epistemic Contextualism and RelativismDisagreement, MiscFirst-Person ContentsPropositions, MiscSitua…Read more
    Epistemic Contextualism and RelativismDisagreement, MiscFirst-Person ContentsPropositions, MiscSituation Semantics
  •  124
    Compositionality, Flexibility, and Context-Dependence
    In Wolfram Hinzen, Edouard Machery & Markus Werning (eds.), Oxford Handbook of Compositionality, Oxford University Press. pp. 175-191. 2012.
    It has often been observed that the meaning of a word may be affected by the other words which occur in the same sentence. How are we to account for this phenomenon of 'semantic flexibility'? It is argued that semantic flexibility reduces to context-sensitivity and does not raise unsurmountable problems for standard compositional accounts. On the other hand, it would be a mistake to assume too simple a view of context-sensitivity. Two basic forms of context-sensitivity are distinguished in the p…Read more
    It has often been observed that the meaning of a word may be affected by the other words which occur in the same sentence. How are we to account for this phenomenon of 'semantic flexibility'? It is argued that semantic flexibility reduces to context-sensitivity and does not raise unsurmountable problems for standard compositional accounts. On the other hand, it would be a mistake to assume too simple a view of context-sensitivity. Two basic forms of context-sensitivity are distinguished in the paper. The second form — sense modulation — shows that, in a sense, there is more in the meaning of the whole than can be derived from the meanings of the parts.
    CompositionalityPredicates and Context-DependenceSemantics-Pragmatics DistinctionThe Scope of Contex…Read more
    CompositionalityPredicates and Context-DependenceSemantics-Pragmatics DistinctionThe Scope of Context-Dependence
  •  10
    Reply to Brabanter
    Response to Brabanter's contribution in the proceedings of the Granada workshop
    Semantics
  • Insinuation et sous-entendu
    Communications 30 95-106. 1979.
  •  294
    Contextual Dependence and Definite Descriptions
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 87 57-73. 1987.
    François Recanati; IV*—Contextual Dependence and Definite Descriptions, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 87, Issue 1, 1 June 1987, Pages 57–74, h.
    Descriptions
  •  737
    Rigidity and direct reference
    Philosophical Studies 53 (1). 1988.
    Russellian and Direct Reference Theories of MeaningSpecific ExpressionsNouns
  •  71
    First Person Thought
    In Julien Dutant, Davide Fassion & Anne Meylan (eds.), Liber Amicorum Pascal Engel, . pp. 506-511. 2014.
    First person thoughts are the sort of thought one may express by using the first person ; they are also thoughts that are about the thinker of the thought. Neither characterization is ultimately satisfactory. A thought can be about the thinker of the thought by accident, without being a first person thought. The alternative characterization of first person thought in terms of first person sentences also fails, because it is circular : we need the notion of a first person thought to account for t…Read more
    First person thoughts are the sort of thought one may express by using the first person ; they are also thoughts that are about the thinker of the thought. Neither characterization is ultimately satisfactory. A thought can be about the thinker of the thought by accident, without being a first person thought. The alternative characterization of first person thought in terms of first person sentences also fails, because it is circular : we need the notion of a first person thought to account for the reference rule governing the first person in language. The paper offers a new characterization of first person thought. A first person thought is a thought which deploys the first person concept, where the first person concept is construed as a special kind of ‘mental file’. Mental files are based on, and their reference determined by, epistemically rewarding (ER) relations in which the subject stands to entities in the environment. In the case of the SELF file, the relevant ER relation is identity. This guarantees that the first-person concept refers to the thinker of the thought in which it is deployed.
    The First-Person PronounImmunity to Error through MisidentificationFirst-Person ContentsCharacter an…Read more
    The First-Person PronounImmunity to Error through MisidentificationFirst-Person ContentsCharacter and Content
  • The Iconicity of Metarepresentations
    In Dan Sperber (ed.), Meta-Representations: a Multidisciplinary Perspective, Oxford University Press. pp. 311-360. 2000.
    Propositions and That-ClausesSubstitutivity in Attitude AscriptionsVarieties of RepresentationIntens…Read more
    Propositions and That-ClausesSubstitutivity in Attitude AscriptionsVarieties of RepresentationIntensionality and OpacityStructured Propositions
  •  30
    Local pragmatics: reply to Mandy Simons
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 60 (5): 493-508. 2017.
    In response to Mandy Simons’ defence of a classical Gricean approach to pragmatic enrichment in terms of conversational implicature, I emphasize the following contrast. Conversational implicatures are generated by a global inference which uses as a premise the fact that the speaker has said that p, but only the triggering inference is global in cases of pragmatic enrichment. What generates the correct interpretation is a process of reconstrual, which locally maps the literal meaning of a constit…Read more
    In response to Mandy Simons’ defence of a classical Gricean approach to pragmatic enrichment in terms of conversational implicature, I emphasize the following contrast. Conversational implicatures are generated by a global inference which uses as a premise the fact that the speaker has said that p, but only the triggering inference is global in cases of pragmatic enrichment. What generates the correct interpretation is a process of reconstrual, which locally maps the literal meaning of a constituent to a modulated meaning and composes that meaning with that of the other constituents. That process is constrained by Gricean considerations but that is true of all pragmatic aspects of interpretation, whether pre-propositional or post-propositional. Just as indexical resolution, though pragmatic and constrained by Gricean considerations, does not fit the two-stage model through which Grice accounts for conversational implicatures, so pragmatic modulation can’t be accounted for in terms of that model despite the fact that, like conversational implicatures and unlike indexical resolution, modulation is pragmatically rather than semantically triggered.
    Conversational Implicature
  • Beyond Analytic Philosophy?
    Stanford French Review 17 197-205. 1993.
    Metaphilosophy, MiscThe Nature of Analytic Philosophy
  •  433
    What is said
    Synthese 128 (1-2): 75--91. 2001.
    A critique of the purely semantic, minimalist notion of 'what is said'.
    Semantic MinimalismThe Scope of Context-DependenceSpeaker Meaning and Linguistic MeaningThe Nature o…Read more
    Semantic MinimalismThe Scope of Context-DependenceSpeaker Meaning and Linguistic MeaningThe Nature of Contents, MiscSemantics-Pragmatics Distinction
  • Primary Pragmatic Processes
    In Asa Kasher (ed.), Pragmatics: Critical Concepts, Routledge. pp. 512-531. 1998.
    Conversational ImplicatureTruth-Conditional TheoriesSemantics-Pragmatics DistinctionSpeaker Meaning …Read more
    Conversational ImplicatureTruth-Conditional TheoriesSemantics-Pragmatics DistinctionSpeaker Meaning and Linguistic MeaningRelevance Theory
  • Direct Reference: From Language to Thought
    Linguistics and Philosophy 19 (1): 91-102. 1996.
    Philosophy of Language
  •  22
    Some Remarks on Explicit Performatives, Indirect Speech Acts, Locutionary Meaning and Truth-value
    In John Searle, F. Kiefer & Manfred Berwisch (eds.), Speech Act Theory and Pragmatics, Dordrecht. pp. 205-220. 1980.
    Speech Acts
  •  1
    Literal meaning — figures
    COMPLETE SET OF FIGURES FOR 'LITERAL MEANING'
    Semantic Phenomena
  • Truth-conditional pragmatics
    In Asa Kasher (ed.), Pragmatics: Critical Concepts, . pp. 509-511. 1998.
    Semantics-Pragmatics DistinctionSpeaker Meaning and Linguistic MeaningThe Scope of Context-Dependenc…Read more
    Semantics-Pragmatics DistinctionSpeaker Meaning and Linguistic MeaningThe Scope of Context-DependenceTruth-Conditional Theories
  •  8
    Philosophie du langage (et de l’esprit)
    Editions Gallimard. 2008.
    Philosophie du langage et philosophie de l'esprit constituent désormais un tout indissociable. Les expressions linguistiques «signifient». Qu'est-ce que cela veut dire? François Recanati distingue trois réponses possibles. Selon la première, signifier c'est (pour une expression linguistique) être associée à des représentations mentales. Selon la deuxième, signifier c'est «faire référence» et renvoyer à quelque chose dans le monde – une réalité extralinguistique. Selon la troisième, enfin, signi…Read more
    Philosophie du langage et philosophie de l'esprit constituent désormais un tout indissociable. Les expressions linguistiques «signifient». Qu'est-ce que cela veut dire? François Recanati distingue trois réponses possibles. Selon la première, signifier c'est (pour une expression linguistique) être associée à des représentations mentales. Selon la deuxième, signifier c'est «faire référence» et renvoyer à quelque chose dans le monde – une réalité extralinguistique. Selon la troisième, enfin, signifier, c'est jouer un rôle distinctif dans cette activité sociale qu'est la parole. La première réponse renvoie aux représentations mentales. Mais qu'est-ce, pour une représentation mentale, que d'avoir un contenu? La vraie question, est-on tenté de penser, est plus générale : qu'est-ce que signifier ou avoir un contenu? Qu'est-ce qu'une représentation (linguistique ou mentale)? Les philosophes contemporains recherchent une théorie du contenu qui soit suffisamment générale pour s'appliquer à la pensée aussi bien qu'au langage. François Recanati nous introduit à leurs efforts, et conclut en faveur de l'approche «pragmatique» inspirée de Wittgenstein. Ce qui fait que la pensée et le langage représentent le monde, c'est avant tout le fait que la pensée et le langage sont dans le monde, qu'ils y ont leur place et y jouent leur rôle.
  •  270
    Does linguistic communication rest on inference?
    Mind and Language 17 (1-2). 2002.
    It is often claimed that, because of semantic underdetermination, one can determine the content of an utterance only by appealing to pragmatic considerations concerning what the speaker means, what his intentions are. This supports ‘inferentialism' : the view that, in contrast to perceptual content, communicational content is accessed indirectly, via an inference. As against this view, I argue that primary pragmatic processes (the pragmatic processes that are involved in the determination of tru…Read more
    It is often claimed that, because of semantic underdetermination, one can determine the content of an utterance only by appealing to pragmatic considerations concerning what the speaker means, what his intentions are. This supports ‘inferentialism' : the view that, in contrast to perceptual content, communicational content is accessed indirectly, via an inference. As against this view, I argue that primary pragmatic processes (the pragmatic processes that are involved in the determination of truth-conditional content) need not involve an inference from premisses concerning what the speaker can possibly intend by his utterance. Indeed, they need not involve any inference at all : communication, I argue, is as direct as perception.
    Linguistic CommunicationContext and Context-Dependence, MiscInferenceSemantics-Pragmatics Distinctio…Read more
    Linguistic CommunicationContext and Context-Dependence, MiscInferenceSemantics-Pragmatics DistinctionEpistemology of TestimonyConsciousness and Content, Misc
  •  108
    Reference through Mental Files : Indexicals and Definite Descriptions
    In Carlo Penco & Filippo Domaneschi (eds.), What Is Said and What Is Not, Stanford. pp. 159-173. 2013.
    Accounts for referential communication (and especially communication by means of definite descriptions and indexicals) in the mental file framework.
    Descriptions, MiscDirect Reference Theories of IndexicalsIndexicals, MiscSpeaker Meaning and Linguis…Read more
    Descriptions, MiscDirect Reference Theories of IndexicalsIndexicals, MiscSpeaker Meaning and Linguistic MeaningMillian Theories of Names
  •  6
    La conjecture de Ducrot, vingt ans après
    In Marion Carel (ed.), Les Facettes du dire : hommage à Oswald Ducrot, Kime. pp. 269-281. 2002.
    Réponse aux objections soulevées par Oswald Ducrot à l'encontre de mon approche "gricéenne" de la performativité.
    PerformativesSpeech Acts
  • La Signalisation du Discours
    Larousse. 1982.
  •  107
    Open quotation revisited
    Philosophical Perspectives 22 (1): 443-471. 2008.
    This paper — a sequel to my 'Open Quotation' (Mind 2001) — is my reaction to the articles discussing open quotation in the special issue of the Belgian Journal of Linguistics edited by P. De Brabanter in 2005
    Quotation
  •  68
    Deixis and Anaphora
    In Zoltan Gendler Szabo (ed.), Semantics Versus Pragmatics, Clarendon Press. pp. 286--316. 2002.
    A defence of the 'pragmatic' theory of anaphora (which stresses the analogy between anaphora and deixis) against an argument put forward by Gareth Evans.
    SemanticsPronouns and AnaphoraAttributive and Referential Uses of DescriptionsIndexicals, MiscQuanti…Read more
    SemanticsPronouns and AnaphoraAttributive and Referential Uses of DescriptionsIndexicals, MiscQuantifiers, MiscReference, Misc
  •  20
    Reply to Dokic
    Response to Dokic's contribution in the proceedings of the Granada workshop
    Philosophy of LinguisticsPhilosophy of Consciousness
  •  117
    Immunity to error through misidentification: What it is and where it comes from
    In Simon Prosser & Francois Recanati (eds.), Immunity to Error Through Misidentification: New Essays, Cambridge University Press. pp. 180--201
    I argue that immunity to error through misidentification primarily characterizes thoughts that are 'implicitly' de se, as opposed to thoughts that involve an explicit self-identification. Thoughts that are implicitly de se involve no reference to the self at the level of content: what makes them de se is simply the fact that the content of the thought is evaluated with respect to the thinking subject. Or, to put it in familiar terms : the content of the thought is a property which the thinking s…Read more
    I argue that immunity to error through misidentification primarily characterizes thoughts that are 'implicitly' de se, as opposed to thoughts that involve an explicit self-identification. Thoughts that are implicitly de se involve no reference to the self at the level of content: what makes them de se is simply the fact that the content of the thought is evaluated with respect to the thinking subject. Or, to put it in familiar terms : the content of the thought is a property which the thinking subject self-ascribes (as in the Loar/Lewis/Chisholm analysis). After answering an objection (to the effect that immunity can affect explicit de se thoughts), I extend the analysis to demonstrative thoughts, which also exhibit the property of immunity to error through misidentification.
    Immunity to Error through MisidentificationThe First-Person PronounSelf-Consciousness in ExperienceB…Read more
    Immunity to Error through MisidentificationThe First-Person PronounSelf-Consciousness in ExperienceBodily AwarenessFirst-Person Contents
  • La Pragmatique (edited book)
    with Anne-Marie Diller
    Larousse. 1979.
  •  248
    Content, Mood, and Force
    Philosophy Compass 8 (7): 622-632. 2013.
    In this survey paper, I start from two classical theses of speech act theory: that speech act content is uniformly propositional and that sentence mood encodes illocutionary force. These theses have been questioned in recent work, both in philosophy and linguistics. The force/content distinction itself – a cornerstone of 20‐century philosophy of language – has come to be rejected by some theorists, unmoved by the famous ‘Frege–Geach’ argument. The paper reviews some of these debates.
    Linguistic ForceQuestionsSpeech ActsThe Unity of the Proposition
  • Prev.
  • 1
  • 2
  • 3
  • 4
  • 5
  • 6
  • 7
  • Next
PhilPeople logo

On this site

  • Find a philosopher
  • Find a department
  • The Radar
  • Index of professional philosophers
  • Index of departments
  • Help
  • Acknowledgments
  • Careers
  • Contact us
  • Terms and conditions

Brought to you by

  • The PhilPapers Foundation
  • The American Philosophical Association
  • Centre for Digital Philosophy, Western University
PhilPeople is currently in Beta Sponsored by the PhilPapers Foundation and the American Philosophical Association
Feedback