Yale University
Department of Philosophy
PhD, 1976
Seoul, Seoul-t'ukpyolsi, Korea (Republic of)
Areas of Specialization
Metaphysics
Asian Philosophy
  •  49
    Deductive, Inductive, Both or Neither?
    Journal of Indian Philosophy 31 (1/3): 303-321. 2003.
  •  33
    Is reductionism expressible?
    In Mario D'Amato, Jay L. Garfield & Tom J. F. Tillemans (eds.), Pointing at the Moon: Buddhism, Logic, Analytic Philosophy, Oxford University Press. pp. 57--69. 2009.
  •  109
    Buddhism as Philosophy: An Introduction
    Hackett Pub. Co.. 2007.
    In this clear, concise account, Siderits makes the Buddhist tradition accessible to a Western audience, offering generous selections from the canonical Buddhist texts and providing an engaging, analytical introduction to the basic tenets of Buddhist thought.
  •  54
    The madhyamaka critique of epistemology II
    Journal of Indian Philosophy 9 (2): 121-160. 1981.
  •  78
    Word meaning, sentence meaning, and apoha
    Journal of Indian Philosophy 13 (2): 133-151. 1985.
  •  11
    Book review (review)
    Journal of Indian Philosophy 8 (2): 111-114. 1980.
  •  86
    The madhyamaka critique of epistemology. I
    Journal of Indian Philosophy 8 (4): 307-335. 1980.
  •  185
    Causation and emptiness in early madhyamaka
    Journal of Indian Philosophy 32 (4): 393-419. 2004.
  •  40
    More things in heaven and earth
    Journal of Indian Philosophy 10 (2): 187-208. 1982.
  •  96
    Nāgārjuna as anti-realist
    Journal of Indian Philosophy 16 (4): 311-325. 1988.
  •  162
    Paleo-compatibilism and buddhist reductionism
    Sophia 47 (1): 29-42. 2008.
    Paleo-compatibilism is the view that the freedom required for moral responsibility is not incompatible with determinism about the factors relevant to moral assessment, since the claim that we are free and the claim that the psychophysical elements are causally determined are true in distinct and incommensurable ways. This is to be accounted for by appealing to the distinction between conventional truth and ultimate truth developed by Buddhist Reductionists. Paleo-compatibilists hold that the ill…Read more
  •  73
  •  156
    Buddhist reductionism
    Philosophy East and West 47 (4): 455-478. 1997.
    While Derek Parfit is aware that his reductionism about persons is anticipated in early Buddhism and Abhidharma, he has not explored that tradition for any clues it might yield concerning the consequences of adopting the position. In this essay, the tradition is used to construct a taxonomy of possible views about persons, and then examine the meta-physical commitments that Buddhist reductionists claim are entailed by their view. While these turn out to be significant, it is argued here that thi…Read more
  •  45
    A note on the early buddhist theory of truth
    Philosophy East and West 29 (4): 491-499. 1979.
  •  286
    An introduction to buddhist ethics: Foundations, values and issues
    with Peter Harvey
    Journal of Chinese Philosophy 31 (3). 2004.
    This systematic introduction to Buddhist ethics is aimed at anyone interested in Buddhism, including students, scholars and general readers. Peter Harvey is the author of the acclaimed Introduction to Buddhism, and his new book is written in a clear style, assuming no prior knowledge. At the same time it develops a careful, probing analysis of the nature and practical dynamics of Buddhist ethics in both its unifying themes and in the particularities of different Buddhist traditions. The book app…Read more
  •  78
    Perceiving particulars: A buddhist defense
    Philosophy East and West 54 (3): 367-382. 2004.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Perceiving Particulars:A Buddhist DefenseMark SideritsIn a recent article in this journal, Monima Chadha claimed that the position of certain Buddhist philosophers concerning the perception of particulars is incoherent.1 Her defense of what she calls a "Nyāya-Kantian" position raises interesting questions concerning how we have knowledge of mind-independent reality. While the view that she subscribes to may well be right, I shall try…Read more
  •  308
    Buddhism and techno-physicalism: Is the eightfold path a program?
    Philosophy East and West 51 (3): 307-314. 2001.
    Recent developments in technology and material culture suggest that physicalism may come to be accepted as the commonsense view of the constitution of persons. Like many other spiritual practices, Buddhism has traditionally relied on a dualist understanding of human nature, according to which persons are made up of both physical and nonphysical entities and events. Would anything central to the Buddhist project be lost if that were replaced by physicalism? Clearly the Yogācāra doctrine of consci…Read more
  •  177
    Beyond compatibilism: A buddhist approach to freedom and determinism
    American Philosophical Quarterly 24 (2): 149-59. 1987.
  •  74
    Ehring on Parfit's relation R
    Analysis 48 (January): 29-32. 1988.
  •  46
    Does a Table Have Buddha-Nature?
    Philosophy East and West 63 (3): 373-386. 2013.
    I argue against the dialetheist interpretation of Madhyamaka propounded by Garfield and Priest, in part on textual grounds, but also on the grounds that their reading completely misses the rhetorical strategy behind the use of contradictions for soteriological ends in the Indian Buddhist tradition.