•  3
    Index
    In Saving Belief: A Critique of Physicalism, Princeton University Press. pp. 175-178. 1987.
  •  268
    De re belief in action
    Philosophical Review 91 (3): 363-387. 1982.
  •  288
    First-personal aspects of agency
    Metaphilosophy 42 (1-2): 1-16. 2011.
    Abstract: On standard accounts, actions are caused by reasons (Davidson), and reasons are taken to be neural phenomena. Since neural phenomena are wholly understandable from a third-person perspective, standard views have no room for any ineliminable first-personal elements in an account of the causation of action. This article aims to show that first-person perspectives play essential roles in both human and nonhuman agency. Nonhuman agents have rudimentary first-person perspectives, whereas hu…Read more
  •  5
    Everyday Concepts as a Guide to Reality
    The Monist 89 (3): 313-333. 2006.
  •  172
    Everyday concepts as a guide to reality
    The Monist 89 (3): 313-333. 2006.
    On September 11, 2001, as everyone knows, the towers of the World Trade Center in New York were attacked. I want to discuss this event in order to motivate a nonreductionist view of the extensions of everyday concepts. Next, I shall set out, and begin to defend, the particular view of nonreductionism that I favor—the Constitution View. Then, I shall consider two venerable metaphysical issues (the nature of vagueness and the mind-independent/mind- dependent distinction) in light of the Constituti…Read more
  •  207
    Christian materialism in a scientific age
    International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 70 (1): 47-59. 2011.
    Many Christians who argue against Christian materialism direct their arguments against what I call ‘Type-I materialism’, the thesis that I cannot exist without my organic body. I distinguish Type-I materialism from Type-II materialism, which entails only that I cannot exist without some body that supports certain mental functions. I set out a version of Type-II materialism, and argue for its superiority to Type-I materialism in an age of science. Moreover, I show that Type-II materialism can acc…Read more
  •  1
    Contents
    In Saving Belief: A Critique of Physicalism, Princeton University Press. 1987.
  •  8
    Book Reviews (review)
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 81 (4): 597-598. 2003.
    Book Information Objects and Persons. Objects and Persons Trenton Merricks. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2001, pp. xii + 203, £30, £14.99. By Trenton Merricks. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Pp. xii + 203. £30, £14.99
  •  68
    Brief Reply to Rosenkrantz’s Comments on my “The Ontological Status of Persons”
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65 (2): 394-396. 2002.
    1. Primary-kind properties. Rosenkrantz does not see how a single primary-kind property can be had by x essentially and by y contingently . He offers a reductio ad absurdum of the view that a primary can be had accidentally or derivatively. The reductio has as a premise the following: “[S]omething has a primarykind property, F-ness, derivatively only if the primary-kind property of a nonderivative F, i.e., the property which determines what a nonderivative F most fundamentally is, is nonderivati…Read more
  •  4
    2. Belief in Cognitive Science
    In Saving Belief: A Critique of Physicalism, Princeton University Press. pp. 23-42. 1987.
  •  63
  •  8
    1. Common Sense and Physicalism
    In Saving Belief: A Critique of Physicalism, Princeton University Press. pp. 1-20. 1987.
  •  39
    Belief ascription and the illusion of depth
    Facta Philosophica 5 (2): 183-201. 2003.
  •  124
    Was Leibniz Entitled to Possible Worlds?
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 15 (1): 57-74. 1985.
    Leibniz has enjoyed a prominent place in the history of thought about possible worlds.' I shall argue that on the feading interpretation of Leibniz's account of contingency — an ingenious interpretation with ample textual support — possible worlds may be invoked by Leibniz only on pain of inconsistency. Leibnizian contingency, as reconstructed in detail by Robert C. Sleigh, Jr.,z will be shown to preclude propositions with different truth-values in different possible worlds.
  •  212
    A metaphysics of ordinary things and why we need it
    Philosophy 83 (1): 5-24. 2008.
    Metaphysics has enjoyed a vigorous revival in the last few decades. Even so, there has been little ontological interest in the things that we interact with everyday—trees, tables, other people.1 It is not that metaphysicians ignore ordinary things altogether. Indeed, they are happy to say that sentences like ‘The daffodils are out early this year’ or ‘My computer crashed again’ are true. But they take the truth of such sentences not to require that a full description of reality mention daffodils…Read more
  •  3
    Acknowledgments
    In Saving Belief: A Critique of Physicalism, Princeton University Press. 1987.
  •  117
    Human Persons as Social Entities
    Journal of Social Ontology 1 (1): 77-87. 2014.
    The aim of this article is to show that human persons belong, ontologically, in social ontology. After setting out my views on ontology, I turn to persons and argue that they have first-person perspectives in two stages (rudimentary and robust) essentially. Then I argue that the robust stage of the first-person persective is social, in that it requires a language, and languages require linguistic communities. Then I extend the argument to cover the rudimentary stage of the first-person perspecti…Read more
  •  67
    Explaining Attitudes: A Practical Approach to the Mind
    Cambridge University Press. 1995.
    Explaining Attitudes offers an important challenge to the dominant conception of belief found in the work of such philosophers as Dretske and Fodor. According to this dominant view beliefs, if they exist at all, are constituted by states of the brain. Lynne Rudder Baker rejects this view and replaces it with a quite different approach - practical realism. Seen from the perspective of practical realism, any argument that interprets beliefs as either brain states or states of immaterial souls is a…Read more
  •  62
    Explaining Attitudes: A Practical Approach to the Mind
    Cambridge University Press. 1995.
    Explaining Attitudes develops a new account of propositional attitudes - practical realism.
  •  85
    Philosophy in Mediis Rebus
    Metaphilosophy 32 (4): 378-394. 2001.
    So, let us begin in the middle of things. There are two senses in which I think that philosophy must begin in the middle of things: The first is epistemological: I think that the Cartesian ideal of finding an absolute starting point without any presuppositions is illusory. The most that we can do is to be aware of our presuppositions; we cannot eliminate them. Wherever we choose to start, we are in the middle of things epistemologically. The second way in which I think that philosophy must begin…Read more
  •  67
    On the mind-dependence of temporal becoming
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 39 (3): 341-357. 1979.
  •  295
    One of the deepest assumptions of Judaism and its offspring, Christianity, is that there is an important difference between human persons and everything else that exists in Creation. We alone are made in God’s image. We alone are the stewards of the earth. It is said in Genesis that we have “dominion over the fish of the sea, and over the birds of the air, and over the cattle, and over all the earth, and over every creeping thing that creeps upon the earth.” It is difficult to see how a traditio…Read more
  •  109
    On Making Things Up
    Philosophical Topics 30 (1): 31-51. 2002.
  •  283
    Making sense of ourselves: self-narratives and personal identity
    Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 15 (1): 7-15. 2016.
    Some philosophers take personal identity to be a matter of self-narrative. I argue, to the contrary, that self-narrative views cannot stand alone as views of personal identity. First, I consider Dennett’s self-narrative view, according to which selves are fictional characters—abstractions, like centers of gravity—generated by brains. Neural activity is to be interpreted from the intentional stance as producing a story. I argue that this is implausible. The inadequacy is masked by Dennett’s ambig…Read more