•  22
    Aristotle’s Theory of Substance (review)
    Philosophical Review 111 (1): 98-101. 2002.
    Michael Wedin’s Aristotle’s Theory of Substance provides an interpretation of primary substance in Metaphysics Book Z that is compatible with the ontology of the Categories. The incompatibilist position holds that primary substance in the Categories is the concrete, individual substance, like Socrates, whereas the title of primary substance in Metaphysics Z goes to the eidos, the form or the species. Hence, the ontology of the Categories is incompatible with the ontology of Metaphysics Z. One co…Read more
  •  13
    Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics (review)
    Ancient Philosophy 5 (1): 113-116. 1985.
  •  15
    (University of New Hampshire, USA)
    In Lilli Alanen & Charlotte Witt (eds.), Feminist Reflections on the History of Philosophy, Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 55. 2004.
  •  1
    "Aristotle", by Jonathan Barnes (review)
    Ancient Philosophy 3 (1): 100. 1983.
  •  210
    Hylomorphism in Aristotle
    Journal of Philosophy 84 (11): 673-679. 1987.
  •  286
    Feminist Reflections on the History of Philosophy (edited book)
    Kluwer Academic Publishers. 2004.
    Feminist work in the history of philosophy has come of age as an innovative field in the history of philosophy. This volume marks that accomplishment with original essays by leading feminist scholars who ask basic questions: What is distinctive of feminist work in the history of philosophy? Is there a method that is distinctive of feminist historical work? How can women philosophers be meaningfully included in the history of the discipline? Who counts as a philosopher? This collection is a uniqu…Read more
  •  2
    CDC Reeves, Substantial Knowledge Reviewed by
    Philosophy in Review 20 (6): 430-431. 2000.
  •  1
    Teleology in Aristotelian Science and Metaphysics
    In Jyl Gentzler (ed.), Method in ancient philosophy, Oxford University Press Uk. 1997.
  •  20
    Power, activity, and being
    In Brad Inwood (ed.), Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy Xxxv: Winter 2008, Oxford University Press. pp. 35--293. 2008.
  •  46
    Aristotle
    Teaching Philosophy 11 (3): 100-102. 1988.
  •  197
    Feminist history of philosophy
    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2008.
    The past twenty five years have seen an explosion of feminist writing on the philosophical canon, a development that has clear parallels in other disciplines like literature and art history. Since most of the writing is, in one way or another, critical of the tradition, a natural question to ask is: Why does the history of philosophy have importance for feminist philosophers? This question assumes that the history of philosophy is of importance for feminists, an assumption that is warranted by t…Read more
  •  15
    Colloquium 7
    Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 11 (1): 249-266. 1995.
  •  126
    Aristotle on Deformed Animal Kinds
    Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 43 83. 2012.
    There is a surprising number of deformed animal kinds mentioned in Aristotle’s biological works. The number is surprising because, according to the standard understanding of deformed animals in Aristotle, it should be zero. And the number is significant because there are just too many deformed kinds at too many classificatory levels mentioned in too many works to dismiss them as a minor aberration or as an infiltration of folk belief into biology proper. This paper has two goals. The first is to…Read more
  •  18
    Aristotle's conception of the mind
    Philosophical Books 36 (2): 81-89. 1995.
  •  48
    Substance among Other Categories
    Philosophical Review 105 (4): 562. 1996.
    This book develops an account of what substance is in terms of the notion of independence. As the authors note, there is a tradition of defining substance as independent that begins with Aristotle. But what notion of independence can provide an adequate definition of substance? The authors find traditional attempts to define independence, including Aristotle’s, inadequate on a number of grounds, and they propose an alternative account. As a preface to this undertaking, the authors consider and r…Read more
  • C.D.C. Reeve, Substantial Knowledge (review)
    Philosophy in Review 20 430-431. 2000.
  •  69
    Aristotle’s Theory of Substance (review)
    Philosophical Review 111 (1): 98-101. 2002.
    Aristotle's doctrines about accidental predication, Accidental identity, Etc., Can be understood as an attempt to state the same view as russell put forward in his theory of descriptions. "a" is predicated accidentally of b when "a to b" has the sense "something that is a is b." this permits scope distinctions which can solve puzzles like that of the masked man, And sophisms involving tense. Aristotle's claim that accidental being is akin to nonexistence resembles russell's account of the presen…Read more
  •  23
    Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics (review)
    Ancient Philosophy 5 (1): 113-116. 1985.
  •  195
    The Metaphysics of Gender
    Oup Usa. 2011.
    The Metaphysics of Gender is a book about gender essentialism: what it is and why it might be true.
  •  21
    Aristotle
    Ancient Philosophy 3 (1): 100-102. 1983.
  •  3
    Powers and possibilities: Aristotle vs. the Megarians
    Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 11 249-266. 1995.
  •  223
    Feminist Metaphysics is the first collection of articles addressing metaphysical issues from a feminist perspective.
  •  13
    Commentary on Charlton
    Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 5 (1): 23-26. 1989.
  •  44
    Aristotle on Female Animals: A Study of the Generation of Animals by Sophia M. Connell
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 55 (1): 157-158. 2017.
    “How can it be that the female is both functional and a failure?”. Sophia Connell’s response comes in the form of a careful, thorough, and philosophically sensitive interpretation of Aristotle’s treatise on animal generation. By pursuing the topic of what Aristotle says about female animals and their role in reproduction, Connell casts light into many difficult corners of his theory: What does it mean to say that the male is the “hê archê [tês] kinêseos” of the generation? How should we think of…Read more