•  44
    One way to help ensure the future of human life on the planet is to reduce the total number of people alive, as a hedge against dangers to the environment. One commentator has proposed withdrawing government and insurance subsidies from all fertile people, to help reduce the number of births. Any proposal of this kind does not, however, offer a solution commensurate with current problems of resource use and carbon emissions. Closing off fertility medicine to some people – or even to all – would …Read more
  •  43
  •  43
    Genetic generations: artificial gametes and the embryos produced with them
    Journal of Medical Ethics 40 (11): 739-740. 2014.
    Certain interventions now permit the derivation of mammalian gametes from stem cells cultivated from either somatic cells or embryos. These gametes can be used in an indefinite cycle of conception in vitro, gamete derivation, conception in vitro, and so on, producing genetic generations that live only in vitro. One commentator has described this prospect for human beings as eugenics, insofar as it would allow for the selection and development of certain traits in human beings. This commentary no…Read more
  •  42
    Should parents be able to select the sexual orientation of their children, if that were possible through prenatal interventions? _Ethics, Sexual Orientation, and Choices about Children_ reviews the history of this debate which started in the 1970s and has been invigorated by scientific reports about the origins of sexual orientation. This book describes the debate and offers an evaluation of key issues in parental rights, children's rights, and family welfare.
  •  42
    Differential diagnosis and mental illness
    Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 7 (4): 327-336. 1982.
    In considering the argument that Thomas Szasz advances on behalf of his claim that there is no mental illness, it becomes evident that despite his stated assumptions, moral valuations are necessarily tied up with assessment of disease. By following his remarks about differential diagnosis, it becomes evident that behavior is the occasion for differential diagnosis, that behavior determines which anatomical deviations are counted as diseases, and that Szasz's insistence on autonomy introduces his…Read more
  •  41
  •  40
    Response to “Cloning and Infertility” by Carson Strong
    Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 8 (3): 364-368. 1999.
    Carson Strong has argued that if human cloning were safe it should be available to some infertile couples as a matter of ethics and law. He holds that cloning by somatic cell nuclear transfer should be available as a reproductive option for infertile couples who could not otherwise have a child genetically related to one member of the couple. In this analysis, Strong overlooks an important category of people to whom his argument might apply, couples he has not failed to consider elsewhere. In th…Read more
  •  40
    What Justifies a Future with Humans in It?
    Bioethics 30 (9): 751-758. 2016.
    Antinatalist commentators recommend that humanity bring itself to a close, on the theory that pain and suffering override the value of any possible life. Other commentators do not require the voluntary extinction of human beings, but they defend that outcome if people were to choose against having children. Against such views, Richard Kraut has defended a general moral obligation to people the future with human beings until the workings of the universe render such efforts impossible. Kraut advan…Read more
  •  40
    Sex, Romance, and Research Subjects: An Ethical Exploration
    American Journal of Bioethics 10 (7): 30-38. 2010.
    Professional standards in medicine and psychology treat concurrent sexual relationships with patients as violations of fiduciary trust, and they sometimes rule out sexual relationships even after a clinical relationship is over. These standards also rule out sex with research subjects who are also patients, but what about nonclinical relationships where there are not always parallels to the standards of clinical medicine? One way to treat sex in nonclinical research relationships is to treat it …Read more
  •  40
    Adoption First? The Disposition of Human Embryos
    Journal of Medical Ethics (6): 2013-101525. 2013.
    Anja Karnein has suggested that because of the importance of respect for persons, law and policy should require some human embryos created in vitro to be available for adoption for a period of time. If no one comes forward to adopt the embryos during that time, they may be destroyed (in the case of embryos left over from fertility medicine) or used in research (in the case of embryos created for that purpose or left over from fertility medicine). This adoption option would increase the number of…Read more
  •  38
    D. Micah Hester thinks the residency match system helps sustain the divide between the haves and the have-nots in healthcare. He believes that the match system channels talent away from the have-nots in a more or less systematic way, damaging moral values in physicians as it goes. As a way of making inroads against these effects, he has asked whether assigning medical school graduates to residencies at random would distribute talent and educational opportunity more broadly and promote desirable …Read more
  •  36
    Getting past nature as a guide to the human sex ratio
    Bioethics 27 (4): 224-232. 2011.
    Sex selection of children by pre-conception and post-conception techniques remains morally controversial and even illegal in some jurisdictions. Among other things, some critics fear that sex selection will distort the sex ratio, making opposite-sex relationships more difficult to secure, while other critics worry that sex selection will tilt some nations toward military aggression. The human sex ratio varies depending on how one estimates it; there is certainly no one-to-one correspondence betw…Read more
  •  34
    Some commentators indirectly challenge the ethics of using synthetic gametes as a way for same-sex couples to have children with shared genetics. These commentators typically impose a moral burden of proof on same-sex couples they do not impose on opposite-sex couples in terms of their eligibility to have children. Other commentators directly raise objections to parenthood by same-sex couples on the grounds that it compromises the rights and/or welfare of children. Ironically, the prospect of sy…Read more
  •  33
    In many ways, we live in propitious times for gay and lesbian people. In 1996, the Supreme Court struck down Colorado law prohibiting any kind of protected status based on sexual orientation. In 2003, the Supreme Court held that states may not criminalize sexual conduct between consenting adults of the same sex in private, so long as no money changes hands. In 2010, the Congress repealed the “Don't Ask, Don't Tell” policy that excluded openly gay men and lesbians from military service. In 2013, …Read more
  •  32
    Assisted Gestation and Transgender Women
    Bioethics 29 (6): 389-397. 2014.
    Developments in uterus transplant put assisted gestation within meaningful range of clinical success for women with uterine infertility who want to gestate children. Should this kind of transplantation prove routine and effective for those women, would there be any morally significant reason why men or transgender women should not be eligible for the same opportunity for gestation? Getting to the point of safe and effective uterus transplantation for those parties would require a focused line of…Read more
  •  32
    What Human Life Amendments Mean and Don't Mean
    American Journal of Bioethics 10 (12): 47-48. 2010.
    A commentary that points out the way in which proposed Human Life Amendments might not prove a bulwark against all abortion. Any such Constitutional amendment would, however, have unintended effects, such as opening the way for embryos to be counted in the federal census, among other things.
  •  31
    Physicians, medical ethics, and capital punishment
    Journal of Clinical Ethics 16 (2): 160. 2005.
  •  30
    Ethics in an Epidemic: Aids, Morality, and Culture
    University of California Press. 1994.
    In this humane and graceful book, philosopher Timothy Murphy offers insight into our attempts--popular and academic, American and non-American, scientific and ...
  •  30
    Letters to the Editor
    Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 80 (2). 2006.
  •  29
    When 'Emergency Contraception' is Neither
    American Journal of Bioethics 7 (8): 7-7. 2007.
    No abstract
  •  29
    The Greatness and Limitations of Freud’s Thought (review)
    International Philosophical Quarterly 21 (1): 111-113. 1981.
  •  27
    Members First: The Ethics of Donating Organs and Tissues to Groups
    with Robert M. Veatch
    Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 15 (1): 50-59. 2006.
    In the United States, people may donate organs and tissues to a family member, friend, or anyone whose specific need becomes known to them. For example, in late 2003 dozens of people came forward to donate a kidney to a professional basketball player known to them only through his sports performances. People may also donate a kidney to no one in particular through a process known as nondirected donation. In nondirected donation, people donate a kidney to the organ allocation system rather than t…Read more
  •  26
    Pathways to genetic parenthood for same-sex couples
    Journal of Medical Ethics 44 (12): 823-824. 2018.
    Researchers are pursuing various ways to synthesise human male and female gametes, which would be useful for people facing infertility. Some people are unable to conceive children with their partner because one of them is infertile in the sense of having an anatomical or physiological deficit. Other people—in same sex couples—may not be individually infertile but situationally infertile in relation to one another. Segers et al have described a pathway towards synthetic gametes that would rely on…Read more
  •  26
    The Tortoise Transformation as a Prospect for Life Extension
    Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 12 (4): 645-649. 2015.
    The value of extending the human lifespan remains a key philosophical debate in bioethics. In building a case against the extension of the species-typical human life, Nicolas Agar considers the prospect of transforming human beings near the end of their lives into Galapagos tortoises, which would then live on decades longer. A central question at stake in this transformation is the persistence of human consciousness as a condition of the value of the transformation. Agar entertains the idea that…Read more
  •  25
    Assent and dissent in 407 research with children
    American Journal of Bioethics 3 (4). 2003.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  25
    So not mothers: responsibility for surrogate orphans
    Journal of Medical Ethics 44 (8): 551-554. 2018.
    The law ordinarily recognises the woman who gives birth as the mother of a child, but in certain jurisdictions, it will recognise the commissioning couple as the legal parents of a child born to a commercial surrogate. Some commissioning parents have, however, effectively abandoned the children they commission, and in such cases, commercial surrogates may find themselves facing unexpected maternal responsibility for children they had fully intended to give up. Any assumption that commercial surr…Read more
  •  25
    Gestation as mothering
    Bioethics 34 (9): 960-968. 2020.
    Some commentators maintain that gestational surrogates are not ‘mothers’ in a way capable of grounding a claim to motherhood. These commentators find that the practices that constitute motherhood do not extend to gestational surrogates. We argue that gestational surrogates should be construed as mothers of the children they bear, even if they fully intend to surrender those children at birth to the care of others. These women stand in a certain relationship to the expected children: they live in…Read more