•  22
    An Introduction to a Theory of Abstract Objects
    Dissertation, University of Massachusetts Amherst. 1981.
    An axiomatic theory of abstract objects is developed and used to construct models of Plato's Forms, Leibniz's Monads, Possible Worlds, Frege's Senses, stories, and fictional characters. The theory takes six primitive metaphysical notions: object ; n-place relations ,G,...); x,...x exemplify F x...x); x exists ; it is necessary that "); and x encodes F "). Properties and propositions are one place and zero place relations, respectively.objects are objects which necessarily fail to exist E!x"). Th…Read more
  • Sorites Paradox
    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. First Published on Jan 17 1997. 2005.
  • Scottish Philosophy in the Nineteenth Century
    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2008.
  •  275
    Fregean senses, modes of presentation, and concepts
    Philosophical Perspectives 15 335-359. 2001.
    of my axiomatic theory of abstract objects.<sup>1</sup> The theory asserts the ex- istence not only of ordinary properties, relations, and propositions, but also of abstract individuals and abstract properties and relations. The
  •  124
    A philosophical conception of propositional modal logic
    Philosophical Topics 21 (2): 263-281. 1993.
    The author revises the formulation of propositional modal logic by interposing a domain of structured propositions between the modal language and the models. Interpretations of the language (i.e., ways of mapping the language into the domain of propositions) are distinguished from models of the domain of propositions (i.e., ways of assigning truth values to propositions at each world), and this contrasts with the traditional formulation. Truth and logical consequence are defined, in the first in…Read more
  •  27
    The Intentional Stance (review)
    Review of Metaphysics 43 (2): 397-400. 1989.
    In this book, Dennett determines just how far we can push the idea that mental states are distinguished by intentionality, that is, by the fact that they have content in virtue of being about, or directed towards, the world at large. Intentionality is characteristic of such states as belief and desire, since all belief is belief of something or that something be the case. In contrast to the physical stance and the design stance, the intentional stance is the predictive attitude or strategy philo…Read more
  •  22
    Philosophy and the world wide web
    American Philosophical Association Newsletter on Computer Use in Philosophy 94 (2): 29-33. 1995.
    In this note, I plan to describe some of the procedures I followed in creating the World Wide Web site for the Metaphysics Research Lab at CSLI. Its URL (Uniform Resource Locator) is.
  •  49
    A Common Ground and Some Surprising Connections
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 40 (S1): 1-25. 2002.
    This paper serves as a kind of field guide to certain passages in the literature which bear upon the foundational theory of abstract objects. The foundational theory assimilates ideas from key philosophers in both the analytical and phenomenological traditions. I explain how my foundational theory of objects serves as a common ground where analytic and phenomenological concerns meet. I try to establish how the theory offers a logic that systematizes a well-known phenomenological kind of entity…Read more
  •  44
    Meinongian type theory and its applications
    Studia Logica 41 (2-3): 297-307. 1982.
    In this paper I propose a fundamental modification of standard type theory, produce a new kind of type theoretic language, and couch in this language a comprehensive theory of abstract individuals and abstract properties and relations of every type. I then suggest how to employ the theory to solve the four following philosophical problems: the identification and ontological status of Frege's Senses; the deviant behavior of terms in propositional attitude contexts; the non-identity of necessarily…Read more
  •  178
    The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy: A developed dynamic reference work
    with Colin Allen and Uri Nodelman
    In James Moor & Terrell Ward Bynum (eds.), Cyberphilosophy: the intersection of philosophy and computing, Blackwell. pp. 210-228. 2002.
    In this entry, the authors outline the goals of a "dynamic reference work", and explain how the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy has been designed to achieve those goals.
  •  175
    This book tackles the issues that arise in connection with intensional logic -- a formal system for representing and explaining the apparent failures of certain important principles of inference such as the substitution of identicals and existential generalization -- and intentional states --mental states such as beliefs, hopes, and desires that are directed towards the world. The theory offers a unified explanation of the various kinds of inferential failures associated with intensional logic b…Read more
  •  256
    The Fundamental Theorem of World Theory
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 43 333-363. 2014.
    The fundamental principle of the theory of possible worlds is that a proposition p is possible if and only if there is a possible world at which p is true. In this paper we present a valid derivation of this principle from a more general theory in which possible worlds are defined rather than taken as primitive. The general theory uses a primitive modality and axiomatizes abstract objects, properties, and propositions. We then show that this general theory has very small models and hence that it…Read more
  •  102
    In this paper, the author shows how one can independently prove, within the theory of abstract objects, some of the most significant claims, hypotheses, and background assumptions found in Kripke's logical and philosophical work. Moreover, many of the semantic features of theory of abstract objects are consistent with Kripke's views — the successful representation, in the system, of the truth conditions and entailments of philosophically puzzling sentences of natural language validates certain K…Read more
  •  122
    Though Frege was interested primarily in reducing mathematics to logic, he succeeded in reducing an important part of logic to mathematics by defining relations in terms of functions. By contrast, Whitehead & Russell reduced an important part of mathematics to logic by defining functions in terms of relations (using the definite description operator). We argue that there is a reason to prefer Whitehead & Russell's reduction of functions to relations over Frege's reduction of relations to funct…Read more
  •  157
    Replies to the critics
    Philosophical Studies 69 (2-3): 231-242. 1993.
    In an author-meets-critics session at the March 1992 Pacific APA meetings, the critics (Christopher Menzel, Harry Deutsch, and C. Anthony Anderson) commented on the author's book *Intensional Logic and the Metaphysics of Intentionality* (Cambridge, MA: MIT/Bradford, 1988). The critical commentaries are published in this issue together with these replies by the author. The author responds to questions concerning the system he proposes, and in particular, to questions concerning the treatment of …Read more
  •  69
    On mally’S alleged heresy:A reply
    History and Philosophy of Logic 13 (1): 59-68. 1992.
    In this paper, I respond to D. Jacquette's paper, "Mally's Heresy and the Logic of Meinong's Object Theory" (History and Philosophy of Logic, 10 (1989): 1-14), in which it is claimed that Ernst Mally's distinction between two modes of predication, as it is employed in the theory of abstract objects, is reducible to, and analyzable in terms of, a single mode of predication plus the distinction between nuclear and extranuclear properties. The argument against Jacquette's claims consists of counte…Read more
  •  229
    Foundations for Mathematical Structuralism
    with Uri Nodelman
    Mind 123 (489): 39-78. 2014.
    We investigate the form of mathematical structuralism that acknowledges the existence of structures and their distinctive structural elements. This form of structuralism has been subject to criticisms recently, and our view is that the problems raised are resolved by proper, mathematics-free theoretical foundations. Starting with an axiomatic theory of abstract objects, we identify a mathematical structure as an abstract object encoding the truths of a mathematical theory. From such foundations,…Read more
  •  55
    Lambert, mally, and the principle of independence
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 25 (1): 447-459. 1985.
    In this paper, the author analyzes critically some of the ideas found in Karel Lambert's recent book, Meinong and the Principle of Independence (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983). Lambert attempts to forge a link between the ideas of Meinong and the free logicians. The link comes in the form of a principle which, Lambert says, these philosophers adopt, namely, Mally's Principle of Independence, which Mally himself later abandoned. Instead of following Mally and attempting to formulate…Read more
  •  167
    In its approach to fiction and fictional discourse, pretense theory focuses on the behaviors that we engage in once we pretend that something is true. These may include pretending to name, pretending to refer, pretending to admire, and various other kinds of make-believe. Ordinary discourse about fictions is analyzed as a kind of institutionalized manner of speaking. Pretense, make-believe, and manners of speaking are all accepted as complex patterns of behavior that prove to be systematic in va…Read more
  •  91
    Fregean Senses, Modes of Presentation, and Concepts
    Noûs 35 (s15): 335-359. 2001.
    Many philosophers, including direct reference theorists, appeal to naively to 'modes of presentation' in the analysis of belief reports. I show that a variety of such appeals can be analyzed in terms of a precise theory of modes of presentation. The objects that serve as modes are identified intrinsically, in a noncircular way, and it is shown that they can function in the required way. It is a consequence of the intrinsic characterization that some objects are well-suited to serve as modes that…Read more
  •  19
    A Philosophical Conception of Propositional Modal Logic
    Philosophical Topics 21 (2): 263-281. 1993.
    The formulation of propositional modal logic is revised by interposing a domain of structured propositions between the modal language and the models. Interpretations of the language (i.e., ways of mapping the language into the domain of propositions) are distinguished from models of the domain of propositions (i.e., ways of assigning truth values to propositions at each world), and this contrasts with the traditional formulation. Truth and logical consequence are defined, in the first instance…Read more
  •  185
    The modal object calculus and its interpretation
    In Maarten de Rijke (ed.), Advances in Intensional Logic, Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 249--279. 1997.
    The modal object calculus is the system of logic which houses the (proper) axiomatic theory of abstract objects. The calculus has some rather interesting features in and of itself, independent of the proper theory. The most sophisticated, type-theoretic incarnation of the calculus can be used to analyze the intensional contexts of natural language and so constitutes an intensional logic. However, the simpler second-order version of the calculus couches a theory of fine-grained properties, relati…Read more
  •  119
    Reflections on the Logic of the Ontological Argument
    Studia Neoaristotelica 4 (1): 28-35. 2007.
    The authors evaluate the soundness of the ontological argument they developed in their 1991 paper. They focus on Anselm’s first premise, which asserts that there is a conceivable thing than which nothing greater can be conceived. After casting doubt on the argument Anselm uses in support of this premise, the authors show that there is a formal reading on which it is true. Such a reading can be used in a sound reconstruction of the argument. After this reconstruction is developed in precise detai…Read more
  •  122
    A comparison of two intensional logics
    Linguistics and Philosophy 11 (1): 59-89. 1988.
    The author examines the differences between the general intensional logic defined in his recent book and Montague's intensional logic. Whereas Montague assigned extensions and intensions to expressions (and employed set theory to construct these values as certain sets), the author assigns denotations to terms and relies upon an axiomatic theory of intensional entities that covers properties, relations, propositions, worlds, and other abstract objects. It is then shown that the puzzles for Montag…Read more
  •  136
    In this paper, we describe "metaphysical reductions", in which the well-defined terms and predicates of arbitrary mathematical theories are uniquely interpreted within an axiomatic, metaphysical theory of abstract objects. Once certain (constitutive) facts about a mathematical theory T have been added to the metaphysical theory of objects, theorems of the metaphysical theory yield both an analysis of the reference of the terms and predicates of T and an analysis of the truth of the sentences of…Read more
  •  212
    Frege, Boolos, and logical objects
    with David J. Anderson
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 33 (1): 1-26. 2004.
    In this paper, the authors discuss Frege's theory of "logical objects" and the recent attempts to rehabilitate it. We show that the 'eta' relation George Boolos deployed on Frege's behalf is similar, if not identical, to the encoding mode of predication that underlies the theory of abstract objects. Whereas Boolos accepted unrestricted Comprehension for Properties and used the 'eta' relation to assert the existence of logical objects under certain highly restricted conditions, the theory of abst…Read more
  •  177
    Logical and analytic truths that are not necessary
    Journal of Philosophy 85 (2): 57-74. 1988.
    The author describes an interpreted modal language and produces some clear examples of logical and analytic truths that are not necessary. These examples: (a) are far simpler than the ones cited in the literature, (b) show that a popular conception of logical truth in modal languages is incorrect, and (c) show that there are contingent truths knowable ``a priori'' that do not depend on fixing the reference of a term.
  •  116
    An alternative theory of nonexistent objects
    with Alan McMichael
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 9 (3): 297-313. 1980.
    The authors develop an axiomatic theory of nonexistent objects and and give a formal semantics for the language of the theory.
  •  486
    Essence and modality
    Mind 115 (459): 659-693. 2006.
    Some recently-proposed counterexamples to the traditional definition of essential property do not require a separate logic of essence. Instead, the examples can be analysed in terms of the logic and theory of abstract objects. This theory distinguishes between abstract and ordinary objects, and provides a general analysis of the essential properties of both kinds of object. The claim ‘x has F necessarily’ becomes ambiguous in the case of abstract objects, and in the case of ordinary objects ther…Read more