•  65
    Aristotle on the Metaphysical Status of Pathe
    Review of Metaphysics 37 (3). 1984.
    CONTEMPORARY discussions of the passions are often puzzlingly pulled in what appear to be opposing directions. We sometimes hold people responsible for their emotions and the actions they perform from them. Yet abnormal behavior is often explained and excused by the person "suffering" an emotional condition. We treat emotions as interruptions or deflections of normal behavior, and yet also consider a person pathological if he fails to act or react from a standard range of emotions. Sometimes emo…Read more
  •  3
    Mind in Action
    Ethics 102 (4): 844-846. 1992.
  •  77
    The Ethics of Collaborative Ambivalence
    The Journal of Ethics 18 (4): 391-403. 2014.
    We are all ambivalent at every turn. “Should I skip class on this gorgeous spring day?” “Do I really want to marry Eric?” Despite being uncomfortable and unsettling, there are some forms of ambivalence that are appropriate and responsible. Even when they seem trivial and superficial, they reveal some of our deepest values, the self-images we would like to project. In this paper, I analyze collaborative ambivalence, the kind of ambivalence that arises from our identity-forming close relationships…Read more
  •  22
    The Deceptive Self: Liars and Layers
    Analyse & Kritik 7 (2): 141-161. 1985.
    This paper gives an account of the picture of the self that saves the phenomena of self-deception. On one theory of the self, the phenomena of selfdeception are incoherent: the self as a unified critically reflective rational inquirer cannot deceive itself. On another theory of the self, the phenomena evaporate: the self as a loosely organized system composed of relatively independent subsystems can be conflicted, mistaken, ignorant, compartmentalized. But it does not deceive itself. Our practic…Read more
  •  41
    From Exasperating Virtues to Civic Virtues
    American Philosophical Quarterly 33 (3). 1996.
  •  85
    The Advantages of Moral Diversity
    Social Philosophy and Policy 9 (2): 38. 1992.
    We are well served, both practically and morally, by moral and ethical diversity. Moral deliberation requires the collaboration of distinctive perspectives: consequentialist, deontological, perfectionist considerations each contribute significant dimensions in determining what is good and what is right; virtue theory highlights the development of reliable ethical character
  •  29
    The Transformations of Persons
    Philosophy 48 (185). 1973.
    In Book IV of The Odyssey , Menelaus tells Telemachus as much as he knows of Odysseus' wanderings. He reports that Odysseus, wanting to learn the end of his travels and needing directions for returning safely home through the dangerous seas, captured Proteus and held fast to him, though Proteus transformed himself into a bearded lion, a snake, a leopard, a bear, running water and finally into a flowering tree. Proteus eventually wearied, and consented to tell Odysseus something of what he wished…Read more
  •  21
    An Open Letter to the Editor
    Philosophy 54 (208). 1979.
  •  386
    Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics (edited book)
    University of California Press. 1980.
    This compilation will mark a high point of excellence in its genre."--Gregory Vlastos, University of California, Berkeley
  •  4
    Philosophers on Education offers us the most comprehensive available history of philosopher's views and impacts on the directions of education. As Amelie Rorty explains, in describing a history of education, we are essentially describing and gaining the clearest understanding of the issues that presently concern and divide us. The essays in this stellar collection are written by some of the finest comtemporary philosophers. Those interested in history of philosophy, epistemology, moral psycholog…Read more
  •  46
    The Politics of Spinoza’s Vanishing Dichotomies
    Political Theory 38 (1). 2010.
    Spinoza's project of showing how the mind can be freed from its passive affects and the State from its divisive factions (E IV.Appendix and V.Preface) ultimately coincides with the aims announced in the subtitle of the Tractatus-Theologico-Politicus (TTP) "to demonstrate that [the] freedom to philosophize does not endanger the piety and obedience required for civic peace." Both projects rest on a set of provisional isomorphic distinctions—between adequate and inadequate ideas, between reason and…Read more
  •  34
    Character (review)
    International Studies in Philosophy 25 (3): 134-135. 1993.
  •  18
    Naturalism, Paradigms, and Ideology
    Review of Metaphysics 24 (4). 1971.
    A close and sympathetic reading of the tensions between naturalism and non-naturalism in Hume's theory shows us something of the ideological issues involved, issues rooted in the differences between the political and social conditions which make naturalism and non-naturalism seem plausible analyses of normative discourse. If we read Hume as a transitional figure, who documented and analyzed a shift in the paradigms of moral situations and problems, we see that the naturalistic controversy is not…Read more
  •  526
    The Identities of Persons (edited book)
    University of California Press. 1976.
    In this volume, thirteen philosophers contribute new essays analyzing the criteria for personal identity and their import on ethics and the theory of action: it ...
  •  166
    Akratic Believers
    American Philosophical Quarterly 20 (2): 175-183. 1983.
    A person has performed an action akratically when he intentionally, voluntarily acts contrary to what he thinks, all things considered, is best to do. This is very misleadingly called weakness of the will; less misleadingly, akrasia of action. I should like to show that there is intellectual as well as practical akrasia. This might, equally misleadingly, be called weakness of belief; less misleadingly, akrasia of belief.
  •  55
    The Directions of Aristotle's Rhetoric
    Review of Metaphysics 46 (1). 1992.
    IN PREPARING A HANDBOOK ON RHETORIC, Aristotle proceeds as he does for a discussion of any craft or practice. After distinguishing it from other closely related arts, he defines its proper aim: that of finding the means that can be used to persuade an audience of any subject whatever. Since the most effective exercise of any craft or faculty is conceptually connected to its fulfilling its norm-defined aims, his counsel is directed to guiding the master craftsman who is responsive to the larger i…Read more
  •  1
    Bringing together a group of outstanding new essays on Aristotle's De Anima, this book covers topics such as the relation between soul and body, sense-perception, imagination, memory, desire, and thought, which present the philosophical substance of Aristotle's views to the modern reader. The contributors write with philosophical subtlety and wide-ranging scholarship, locating their interpretations firmly within the context of Aristotle's thought as a whole. The paperback edition includes an add…Read more
  • Survival and Identity (edited book)
    University of California Press. 1976.
  •  34
    Rousseau's Therapeutic Experiments
    Philosophy 66 (258). 1991.
    ‘Our passions are psychological instruments,’ Rousseau says, ‘with which nature has armed our hearts for the defence of our persons and of all that is necessary for our well-being. [But] the more we need external things, the more we are vulnerable to obstacles that can overwhelm us; and the more numerous and complex our passions become. They are naturally proportionate to our needs.’
  •  252
    Where does the akratic break take place?
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 58 (4). 1980.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  20
    Political Sources of Emotions: Greed and Anger
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy 22 (1): 21-33. 1998.
  •  89
    The Use and Abuse of Morality
    The Journal of Ethics 16 (1): 1-13. 2012.
    Both morality and theories of morality play many distinctive—and sometimes apparently conflicting—functions: they identify and prohibit wrongful aggression; they chart and analyze basic duties; they present ideals for emulation; they set the terms or justice, rights and entitlements; they characterize the norms of basic decency and neighborliness. Since many of these can, in practice, come into conflict with one another, morality provides guidance for integrating priorities. Claims to morality c…Read more
  •  149
    The two faces of stoicism: Rousseau and Freud
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 34 (3): 335-356. 1996.
    The Two Faces of Stoicism: Rousseau and Freud AMI~LIE OKSENBERG RORTY Nor do the Stoics mean that the soul of their wisest man resists the first visions and sudden fantasies that surprise [him]: but [he] rather consents that, as it were to a natural subjection, he yields .... So likewise in other passions, always provided his opinions remain safe and whole, and.., his reason admit no tainting or alteration, and he in no whit consents to his fright and sufferance. Montaigne, Essays, I. 1 THE STOI…Read more
  •  140
    Explaining Emotions (edited book)
    University of California Press. 1980.
    The philosopher must inform himself of the relevant empirical investigation to arrive at a definition, and the scientist cannot afford to be naive about the..
  •  10
    Persons as Rhetorical Categories
    Social Research: An International Quarterly 54. 1987.
  • The Many Faces of Philosophy. Reflections from Plato to Arendt
    Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 66 (2): 393-393. 2004.