•  254
    Essays on Aristotle's De anima (edited book)
    Oxford University Press. 1995 [1992].
    Bringing together a group of outstanding new essays on Aristotle's De Anima, this book covers topics such as the relation between soul and body, sense-perception, imagination, memory, desire, and thought, which present the philosophical substance of Aristotle's views to the modern reader. The contributors write with philosophical subtlety and wide-ranging scholarship, locating their interpretations firmly within the context of Aristotle's thought as a whole.u.
  •  47
    Self-deception, akrasia and irrationality
    In Jon Elster (ed.), The Multiple self, Cambridge University Press. 1985.
  •  147
    From Passions to Emotions and Sentiments
    Philosophy 57 (220). 1982.
    During the period from Descartes to Rousseau, the mind changed. Its domain was redefined; its activities were redescribed; and its various powers were redistributed. Once a part of cosmic Nous, its various functions delimited by its embodied condition, the individual mind now becomes a field of forces with desires impinging on one another, their forces resolved according to their strengths and directions. Of course since there is no such thing as The Mind Itself, it was not the mind that changed…Read more
  •  33
    Varieties of Pluralism in a Polyphonic Society
    Review of Metaphysics 44 (1). 1990.
    NO SOCIETY, NO COMMUNITY can operate without the contributions of distinctive types of mentalities and talents. No society or community is just unless it acknowledges and rewards the contributions of distinctive types of perspectives.
  •  41
    Essential Possibilities in the Actual World
    Review of Metaphysics 25 (4). 1972.
    While this treatment of modalities captures some of the characteristics of our use of "necessary" and "possible," there are important features that are not captured unless we complicate the analysis, and expand the notation. My remarks are not made as a criticism of the possible worlds gambit, but rather as a challenge to formulate a finer network of distinctions to capture notions that now elude us. And there is precedent for this: Plantinga's attempt to distinguish modalities de dicto and de r…Read more
  •  24
    Persons, Policies, and Bodies
    International Philosophical Quarterly 13 (1): 63-80. 1973.
  •  148
    The social and political sources of akrasia
    Ethics 107 (4): 644-657. 1997.
    Akrasia is not always --or only-- a solitary failure to act on a person's judgment of what is, all things considered, best. Nor is it always a species of moral or ethical failure prompted by a form of irrationality. It is often prompted by social support and sustained by structuring political institutions
  •  125
    The Many Faces of Evil: Historical Perspectives (edited book)
    Routledge. 2001.
    This is the first anthology to present the full range of the many forms evil. Amelie Rorty has assembled a collection of readings that include not only the most common forms of evil, such as vice, sin, cruelty and crime, but also some which are less well known, such disobedience and willfulness. The readings are drawn from a rich array of historical, philosophical, theological, literary, dramatic, psychological and legal perspectives. Amelie Rorty's introductions to the readings sets each one in…Read more
  •  65
    Aristotle on the Metaphysical Status of Pathe
    Review of Metaphysics 37 (3). 1984.
    CONTEMPORARY discussions of the passions are often puzzlingly pulled in what appear to be opposing directions. We sometimes hold people responsible for their emotions and the actions they perform from them. Yet abnormal behavior is often explained and excused by the person "suffering" an emotional condition. We treat emotions as interruptions or deflections of normal behavior, and yet also consider a person pathological if he fails to act or react from a standard range of emotions. Sometimes emo…Read more
  •  3
    Mind in Action
    Ethics 102 (4): 844-846. 1992.
  •  77
    The Ethics of Collaborative Ambivalence
    The Journal of Ethics 18 (4): 391-403. 2014.
    We are all ambivalent at every turn. “Should I skip class on this gorgeous spring day?” “Do I really want to marry Eric?” Despite being uncomfortable and unsettling, there are some forms of ambivalence that are appropriate and responsible. Even when they seem trivial and superficial, they reveal some of our deepest values, the self-images we would like to project. In this paper, I analyze collaborative ambivalence, the kind of ambivalence that arises from our identity-forming close relationships…Read more
  •  22
    The Deceptive Self: Liars and Layers
    Analyse & Kritik 7 (2): 141-161. 1985.
    This paper gives an account of the picture of the self that saves the phenomena of self-deception. On one theory of the self, the phenomena of selfdeception are incoherent: the self as a unified critically reflective rational inquirer cannot deceive itself. On another theory of the self, the phenomena evaporate: the self as a loosely organized system composed of relatively independent subsystems can be conflicted, mistaken, ignorant, compartmentalized. But it does not deceive itself. Our practic…Read more
  •  85
    The Advantages of Moral Diversity
    Social Philosophy and Policy 9 (2): 38. 1992.
    We are well served, both practically and morally, by moral and ethical diversity. Moral deliberation requires the collaboration of distinctive perspectives: consequentialist, deontological, perfectionist considerations each contribute significant dimensions in determining what is good and what is right; virtue theory highlights the development of reliable ethical character
  •  29
    The Transformations of Persons
    Philosophy 48 (185). 1973.
    In Book IV of The Odyssey , Menelaus tells Telemachus as much as he knows of Odysseus' wanderings. He reports that Odysseus, wanting to learn the end of his travels and needing directions for returning safely home through the dangerous seas, captured Proteus and held fast to him, though Proteus transformed himself into a bearded lion, a snake, a leopard, a bear, running water and finally into a flowering tree. Proteus eventually wearied, and consented to tell Odysseus something of what he wished…Read more
  •  41
    From Exasperating Virtues to Civic Virtues
    American Philosophical Quarterly 33 (3). 1996.
  •  21
    An Open Letter to the Editor
    Philosophy 54 (208). 1979.
  •  386
    Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics (edited book)
    University of California Press. 1980.
    This compilation will mark a high point of excellence in its genre."--Gregory Vlastos, University of California, Berkeley
  •  4
    Philosophers on Education offers us the most comprehensive available history of philosopher's views and impacts on the directions of education. As Amelie Rorty explains, in describing a history of education, we are essentially describing and gaining the clearest understanding of the issues that presently concern and divide us. The essays in this stellar collection are written by some of the finest comtemporary philosophers. Those interested in history of philosophy, epistemology, moral psycholog…Read more
  •  46
    The Politics of Spinoza’s Vanishing Dichotomies
    Political Theory 38 (1). 2010.
    Spinoza's project of showing how the mind can be freed from its passive affects and the State from its divisive factions (E IV.Appendix and V.Preface) ultimately coincides with the aims announced in the subtitle of the Tractatus-Theologico-Politicus (TTP) "to demonstrate that [the] freedom to philosophize does not endanger the piety and obedience required for civic peace." Both projects rest on a set of provisional isomorphic distinctions—between adequate and inadequate ideas, between reason and…Read more
  •  34
    Character (review)
    International Studies in Philosophy 25 (3): 134-135. 1993.
  •  18
    Naturalism, Paradigms, and Ideology
    Review of Metaphysics 24 (4). 1971.
    A close and sympathetic reading of the tensions between naturalism and non-naturalism in Hume's theory shows us something of the ideological issues involved, issues rooted in the differences between the political and social conditions which make naturalism and non-naturalism seem plausible analyses of normative discourse. If we read Hume as a transitional figure, who documented and analyzed a shift in the paradigms of moral situations and problems, we see that the naturalistic controversy is not…Read more
  •  526
    The Identities of Persons (edited book)
    University of California Press. 1976.
    In this volume, thirteen philosophers contribute new essays analyzing the criteria for personal identity and their import on ethics and the theory of action: it ...
  •  166
    Akratic Believers
    American Philosophical Quarterly 20 (2): 175-183. 1983.
    A person has performed an action akratically when he intentionally, voluntarily acts contrary to what he thinks, all things considered, is best to do. This is very misleadingly called weakness of the will; less misleadingly, akrasia of action. I should like to show that there is intellectual as well as practical akrasia. This might, equally misleadingly, be called weakness of belief; less misleadingly, akrasia of belief.
  •  55
    The Directions of Aristotle's Rhetoric
    Review of Metaphysics 46 (1). 1992.
    IN PREPARING A HANDBOOK ON RHETORIC, Aristotle proceeds as he does for a discussion of any craft or practice. After distinguishing it from other closely related arts, he defines its proper aim: that of finding the means that can be used to persuade an audience of any subject whatever. Since the most effective exercise of any craft or faculty is conceptually connected to its fulfilling its norm-defined aims, his counsel is directed to guiding the master craftsman who is responsive to the larger i…Read more