•  100
    ''Deterrent Punishment and Respect for Persons''
    Ohio State Journal of Criminal Law 8 (2): 369-384. 2011.
    This article defends deterrence as an aim of punishment. Specifically, I contend that a system of punishment aimed at deterrence (with constraints to prohibit punishing the innocent or excessively punishing the guilty) is consistent with the liberal principle of respect for offenders as autonomous moral persons. I consider three versions of the objection that deterrent punishment fails to respect offenders. The first version, raised by Jeffrie Murphy and others, charges that deterrent punishment…Read more
  •  153
    Punishment
    Analysis 77 (3). 2016.
    Philosophical writing about the legal practice of punishment has traditionally focused on two central questions: what (if anything) justifies the practice of tr.
  • ''Obligation''
    In James E. Crimmins (ed.), The Bloomsbury Encyclopedia of Utilitarianism, Bloomsbury Academic. 2013.
  •  42
    Education, Civic Empowerment, and Race
    Social Philosophy Today 31 163-168. 2015.
    Meira Levinson’s No Citizen Left Behind is a thoughtful, accessible, philosophically rich look at civic education in U.S. schools. The book’s central claims are, on the whole, quite persuasive. In the interests of fostering further discussion, this essay raises some questions about the book’s accounts of racial microaggressions in schools, the extent of authenticity in student experiences, and the practice of code-switching.
  •  107
    Ex‐offender Restrictions
    Journal of Applied Philosophy 31 (1): 33-48. 2014.
    Individuals convicted of crimes are often subject to numerous restrictions — on housing, employment, the vote, public assistance, and other goods — well after they have completed their sentences, and in some cases permanently. The question of whether — and if so, when — ex-offender restrictions are morally permissible has received surprisingly little philosophical scrutiny. This article first examines the significance of completing punishment, of paying one's debt to society, and contends that w…Read more
  •  23
    The Moral Permissibility of Punishment
    Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2014.
    The Moral Permissibility of Punishment The legal institution of punishment presents a distinctive moral challenge because it involves a state’s infliction of intentionally harsh, or burdensome, treatment on some of its members—treatment that typically would be considered morally impermissible. Most of us would agree, for instance, that it is typically impermissible to imprison people, to […].
  •  116
    Punishment, Contempt, and the Prospect of Moral Reform
    Criminal Justice Ethics 32 (1): 1-18. 2013.
    This paper objects to certain forms of punishments, such as supermax confinement, on grounds that they are inappropriately contemptuous. Building on discussions in Kant and elsewhere, I flesh out what I take to be salient features of contempt, features that make contempt especially troubling as a form of moral regard and treatment. As problematic as contempt may be in the interpersonal context, I contend that it is especially troubling when a person is treated contemptuously by her political com…Read more
  •  142
    Fair Play, Political Obligation, and Punishment
    Criminal Law and Philosophy 5 (1): 53-71. 2011.
    This paper attempts to establish that, and explain why, the practice of punishing offenders is in principle morally permissible. My account is a nonstandard version of the fair play view, according to which punishment 's permissibility derives from reciprocal obligations shared by members of a political community, understood as a mutually beneficial, cooperative venture. Most fair play views portray punishment as an appropriate means of removing the unfair advantage an offender gains relative to…Read more
  •  3
    ''Hard Times After Hard Time''
    with Nora Wikoff
    In Joanna Crosby David Bzdak & Seth Vannatta (eds.), The Wire and Philosophy, Open Court Books. 2013.